email me
|
|
By Susan J. Fleck. Spring, 2005 – Copyright 2016 by Susan J. Fleck
In a democracy, the individual enjoys not only the ultimate power but
carries the ultimate responsibility. --Norman Cousins
The worth of the state, in the long run, is the worth of the
individuals composing it.
--John Stuart
Mill
As I would not be a slave, so I would not be a master. This expresses my idea of democracy. --Abraham
Lincoln
Democracy is based upon the conviction that there are extraordinary
possibilities in ordinary people. --Harry Emerson Fosdick
But society has now fairly got the better of individuality; and the
danger which threatens human nature is not the excess, but the deficiency, of
personal Impulses and preferences. --John Stuart Mill
Remember, democracy never lasts long. It soon wastes, exhausts, and
murders itself. There never was a democracy yet that did not commit suicide. --John Quincy Adams
One of
the major problems in the study of philosophy is commonly known as "the
one and the many," or "the one over the many." In studying real and imagined Greek cities in
the classical period, it is an interesting quest to try to determine to what degree
these cities were able to, or not able to, balance the needs of the one
individual with the many inhabitants comprising a city. Plato, in the Republic, applies his theory of Forms, which has everything to do
with the problem of the one and the many, by outlining what he considers to be
an ideal "good" city full of harmony, justice, and beauty. Kreon, in the mythical city of Thebes in the Antigone, applies his right of kingship
in an attempt to produce harmony among his city's dwellers. The citizens of the
real city of Athens in the fifth century B.C., and within her sister colonies, through applying democratic principles, achieved
a marvelous advancement in human culture with a synergistic balance between their
personal and public lives. They produced a harmonious society that many wish
could be emulated in lieu of some of the modern, materialistic societies we
find ourselves enmeshed within today. However, these three models of Greek cities
had tremendous flaws: In mythical
Thebes, through inheritance, a tyrant emerges on the throne and his attempt to
force harmony on the city results in the opposite effect; the harmony realized
in fifth century Athens and her colonies was at the expense of about
eighty-five percent of the population; and the engineered harmony in the Republic strips the humanity from all of
its inhabitants, thusly falling far short of any ideal Form of the Good.
Plato, in
the Republic, through the dialectic
voice of Socrates, attempts to discover the nature of Justice. Thrasymachus
declares that justice is the advantage of the stronger—of the established
government (Rep. 1.338c-e). Kreon, in the Antigone, agrees with this sentiment: "Any man who breaks laws
. . . thinks he can give orders to stronger men, gains no praise from me"
(Ant. 805-8), and again,
"Nations belong to the men with power" (Ant. 888). However,
Thrasymachus adds the qualifier "a ruler in the precise sense,"
meaning that justice prevails for the rulers only when they rule correctly to
their own advantage (Rep.
1.341a). Kreon, unfortunately, did not
have good sense to know that his decrees were of the utmost disadvantage to his
own life as well as those close to him and the citizens at large.
Plato determines that Justice is a kind of excellence
of the soul—health, beauty, and well-being of the soul—and excellent souls will
cause one to live well and therefore be happy.
The opposite then, injustice, is disease, ugliness, and weakness of the
soul, that causes one to live badly and to be unhappy (Rep. 1.353d-e). If there is
dissention within a group, or if one is at odds with himself, then nothing can
be achieved; the excellence is absent in such groups and individuals and there
is therefore a lack of justice (Rep.
1.352a). However, this argument alone
does not define what justice is nor does it prove that unjust men, who often
have more wealth and power than those who perform just deeds, are necessarily
unhappy.
Plato expands the discussion to discover what
comprises justice in the city. This strategy is appropriate for Plato because
the Form of the City correlates directly to the Form of a Man. Just as there are three parts to
individual souls—the appetitive
drives and desires, the spirited
emotions, and reasonable thinking—so,
too, in the city there is the corresponding money-making, auxiliary, and
deliberative functions. Therefore, the
cause of strife and internal struggles within the individual is the same kind
of thing that destroys the harmony of a city.
When one's appetites conspire to cause one to act contrary to reason, a
"civil war of the soul" ensues when the spirited part is not aligned
with the reasonable part (Rep.
4.440a-441c). With this analogy, Plato
describes the proper city to be divided into three hard class structures with
auxiliary soldiers as protectors to be aligned with the guardian-rulers and the
third class includes all the rest of the population including money-makers,
women, foreigners, and slaves. Justice
is now defined in the city as when each of the three classes fulfills its own
task and when individuals restrict themselves to one craft. This same kind of
justice and harmony ensues within individuals when each part of one's soul
fulfills its own task and when the reasonable, wise part rules on behalf of the
whole soul (Rep. 2.370b-c 4.441d-e).
It
is ironic, as Lewis Mumford relates, that Plato uses Socrates to insist on the
division of labor to achieve functional perfection and splitting up of social
roles. Had this been the society Socrates was born into, he would have remained
a stonecutter all his life and would have been considered unfit even to ask
questions about any other concerns. It
is as if Plato learned nothing from all that fifth-century Athens had to teach him. From the perspective
of the Republic, wholeness can only
be achieved by the hive and not within an individual, so the individual must be
sacrificed for the sake of the polis (174). Within Plato's epistemological
scheme, the study of mathematics ranks high and that of numbers themselves even higher. Mumford rightly
judges: "The image of the city that captivated him was a geometric
absolute. . . . So strictly did Plato sort out the classes in his ideal city .
. . that he returned to the order of an insect community, whose social
adaptations are sealed in biological structures . . ." (174-5).
Socrates
supposes that a city is established because individuals need many things and no
one is self-sufficient. He describes
several things that one needs, such as shelter, food, and clothing. Glaucon objects that this city of bare
necessities is "a city of pigs" and he wants to test the limit of
Justice by having Socrates imagine building up a luxurious city (Rep. 2.369b-372e). This is the cause of war, Socrates explains,
when small cities are no longer large enough to provide for luxuries and
sustain the growing population needed to provide for such things desired beyond
bare necessities. Thus cities will need to annex their neighbor's land and they
will each need a class of well educated and well trained guardian-soldiers (Rep. 373d). However, according to Lewis
Mumford, this is a foreign notion to the Greek village out of which Greek
cities sprang forth. The self-contained village just wanted to be left alone
and was not interested in conquering others. When Greek cities began to
colonize in order to limit the size of the population, Mumford suggests that
the purpose of colonization was to retain the sense of family and village
affiliation rather than because of the limitations that geography placed on them
to fulfill needs for food and water and such (131-2). Richard Braun also
expresses that the Athenian city-state was based on kinship (5). Certainly,
Antigone obeyed what she thought was a higher law of kinship in honoring her
brother with a proper burial, opposing Kreon's decree to leave him unburied (Ant. 51-55, 87-90, 95-96).
Another
factor to consider when critiquing Plato's emphasis and glorification of war
and soldiering is that the Athens and sister colonies of his time would
probably have seemed like a city of pigs to Glaucon, if one is basing such a
judgment on physical structures and lack of luxurious amenities. Mumford points
out that the housing and sanitary facilities well into the fourth century were
primitive (129). Also, there were plenty
of naturally defensible sites to found new Greek cities, making them less in
need of engineering skills, massive walls, and large armed forces. Poor peasants and shepherds, without any
tempting surplus in the cities, could not be easily bribed or exploited; thus
there was no need for a strict centrally controlled type of government.
Therefore, a looser organization evolved in the Greek cities initiating a
prevalence of personal independence and self-reliance. As Mumford expresses:
"The Greek poleis in their best days had no great surplus of goods: what
they had was a surplus of time, that is, leisure . . . available for
conversation, sexual passion, intellectual reflection, and esthetic
delight" (127).
A
remarkable change in culture took place by the end of the fifth century B.C. in
Greece.
The human mind became conscious of itself and old customs and laws were laid
open to the scrutiny of reason. Even the gods changed to meet these new human
standards and they were molded either to the human caste or slightly larger, in
some cases made to seem ridiculous or contemptible. Citizens were attracted to
and made pilgrimages to the contest, religious, and health centers of Olympia, Delphi, and Cos.
This, in turn, widened the horizons and deepened the conversations for those
who ventured forth from their own more static cities (Mumford 128-143). Within
the Greek city of this period, each citizen participated fully in every aspect
of common life, from the contests, to law courts, to performing in the plays or
singing in the chorus. The result of all of this, Mumford tells us, "was
not merely a torrential outpouring of ideas and images in drama, poetry,
sculpture, painting, logic, mathematics, and philosophy; but a collective life
more highly energized, more heightened in its capacity for esthetic expression
and rational evaluation, than had ever been achieved before" (138).
For
the citizen of Athens, then, it seems that there is a high degree of harmony
between one’s individual needs for a fully actualized life and providing for
the needs of the many in the city by actively participating in all aspects of
public life. The education of the "whole man" during this period took
place not in any special academy or in a rigid course of studies that Plato
proposed for the rulers of the Republic, "but in every activity, every
public duty, in every meeting place and encounter. Work and leisure, theory and
practice, private life and public life were in rhythmic interplay"
(Mumford 168-9).
However,
the business men, the slaves, the foreigners, and the women were excluded from participation
in Athenian democracy. At its height, less than fifteen percent of the population
was citizens (Mumford 135, 153-4). The
Athenian slave had legal protection and had a chance to buy his freedom
(Webster 61). Nevertheless, a slave in any society would hardly consider that
his needs were met or in any way balanced with what he was forced to
contribute. Because there was an international port in the greater Athens area, this was a
thriving industrial and commercial center. As a result, the population of
resident foreigners grew (Webster 56). Since, by definition, a citizen could
not participate in commerce, this faction of the populace, reduced to the
status of irresponsible, second-class citizens, became more and more
disenfranchised (Mumford 129). Marriages were arranged by the partners' fathers
and control of the property that the wife brought into the marriage was
immediately passed to her husband. The women were responsible for the small
children, for female slaves, for spinning, and weaving, and for much to do with
provisioning and preparing food (Webster 64). But she was not a citizen and
thus was excluded from the good life.
Ismene
certainly knew her place, when she pleaded with her sister, Antigone, to not go
against Kreon's edict: "No, we should be sensible: we are women, born
unfit to battle men . . . No, we must obey, even in this . . ." (Ant.
73-7). Kreon is threatened by the
thought of any woman getting the better of him. In a heated discussion with
Haimon, he admonishes: "I'm alive though, and no woman will rule me. . . .
Now they'll have to be women and know their place" (Ant. 646; 716). "Nothing is worse than lack of
leadership. . . . That's why we have to defend orderly people, and never let
women get the better of us. If we must fall, better to fall to a real man and
not be called worse than women" (Ant. 815-24).
One
positive aspect of Plato's Republic
is that it is recognized that women should not be excluded from the
management-ruling class and that women, just as much as men, can be born with
the aptitudes and talents needed to fulfill specific roles (5.455d).
Nevertheless, Plato strips women and men of their dignity and humanity with the
form of controlled and regimented communal living he prescribes for the
auxiliaries. The wives and children and property are to be all held in common
to all the men. Plato compares "successful" procreation of humans
with breeding programs of birds and dogs: ". . . the best men must have
intercourse with the best women as frequently as possible" and the
inferior offspring of lesser men and women are not to be taken to the
"rearing pen" in order to have the best possible "herd"
(5.457d-460c). So, inferior infants are as disposable as inferior or lame dogs.
This
controlled communal living fulfills two purposes in the ideal Republic. First, everyone will
essentially be related to everyone else, since no one knows who is whose
parents or children, and thusly, there will be "common feelings of
pleasure and pain" to provide the bonds to hold the community together.
Second, since they own nothing except their own bodies, there will be none of
the dissention that comes with the territory of possessions, wealth, children
and families (5.462a-64e). This extreme amount of control was necessary only
for the guardian class, the most important for the protection of the Republic
and from which the rulers would be chosen. When Socrates' interlocutors argued
that the guardians could not be happy with such arrangements, he justifies this
strategy for producing harmony between the one and the many:
. . . it is not the law's concern to
make some one group in the city outstandingly happy but to contrive to spread
happiness throughout the city, by bringing the citizens into harmony with each
other by persuasion or compulsion, and to make them share with each other the
benefits which each group can confer upon the community. (7.519e-520a)
Other
controls are necessary in the Republic to ensure that the auxiliaries and
rulers will become the best they can possibly be. One takes the form of a
myth—the noble lie—a device used to instill a sense of pride in each person's
station in life, and to prevent them from desiring possessions; so each person of
this class believes he or she is formed from gold "as a gift from the
gods" and therefore one has no need of additional gold. In addition, it
would be "impious for them to defile this divine possession" by
mixing it with any human kind of gold (3.414c-416e). Censorship is another
control. Story tellers and artists who portray any bad images of the gods must
be rejected. A serious offense is to indicate that the gods lie or change
forms. Plato's God Forms are "as far as is possible best and most
beautiful . . . always simply in his own form" (2.377c-383a). Furthermore,
any character portrayal that is "vicious, mean, unrestrained, or
graceless" is to be rejected, while the "beautiful and the
graceful" is to be promoted in order to nurture the souls of the students
such that they, too, will become "both good and beautiful in
character" (3.401b-e).
Plato
had great distain for poetry and drama, which were merely imitations three
times removed from anything real. He claims, through Socrates' voice, that
poetry panders to the parts of men that are "unreasonable, idle and
friendly to cowardice," and poetic imitation fosters excessive sex, anger,
and desires (10.604d-606d). He is concerned that if one indulges in the
pleasure of poetry or drama, then one will be tempted toward action beyond that
of the golden mean. Mumford judges that the Delphic doctrine of the golden mean
was a big achievement in the height of Athenian culture; this principle applied
to cities as well as for individuals (141, 167). Plato defines the right kind
of love as loving "a well-behaved and beautiful person with moderation and
restraint . . . [with] nothing frenzied or licentious about it"
(3.403a-b). According to Plato, one should not take excessive care for the
body; one should be harmonized in respect to one's spirited nature as well as
wisdom-loving nature, lest one become too rigid or too soft; one should not be
money-loving or mean; and one should partake in pleasures of all kinds only
with moderation" (3.407c, 3.410d-e, 6.486b, 8.559b-c). He was concerned
that if guardians partake in drama then they would be imitating mean or
shameful actions; if they enjoy this imitation they may then "come to
enjoy the reality" (3.395b-d).
Plato
thought that a city could attain achievement of harmony and the golden mean
only when political power and philosophy coalesce, only when philosophers come
to rule as kings (5.473d). G.M.A. Grube interprets this to mean not that a king
needs to be a metaphysician in the strict sense of the term philosopher, but
rather, that "a statesman needs to be a thinker, a lover of truth, beauty,
and the Good, with a highly developed sense of values" (133). In addition
to these qualities, philosophers do not wish to govern; but they must be forced
to climb back into the cave to benefit all others who do not yet know the real world (Rep. 7.519d, 520c). It would
be best if each individual had divine intelligence within him to rule his soul,
but if that is not the case, then one must be enslaved to philosopher kings who
do have the divine rule within themselves (9.590c-d). At this point, Plato has
set up the ideal "good" city with properly educated philosopher kings
who produce laws aimed at harmony and moderation and with auxiliaries to ensure
enactment of such laws.
However,
even an ideal city will eventually decline, Socrates laments, and he goes on to
describe how each of the five types of governments corresponds with the five
types of men's souls, and how each type of government and type of man devolves
into the next lower form (4.445c, 8.546b
ff). The two worst forms of government, according to Plato, are democracy and
dictatorship inhabited with souls that are correspondingly wretched and at odds
with themselves. Democracy comes about when the poor are victorious in a
revolution against the wealthy in an oligarchy. The problem now becomes too
much freedom for an individual to "arrange his own life in any manner that
pleases him" (8.555d-557b). Widespread indulgence in "useless
pleasures" and lack of discipline within individual souls leads to corrupt
and inept rulers who pretend to pander to individual's desires (8. 561c-d). With
things out of control, the populace seeks a champion to straighten things out.
They elevate this champion, who becomes their leader through hints of wealth
redistribution and cancelled debts. He stirs up a war so the people will cling
to their need of him and he turns into a dictator (8.562b-567a). Ironically,
though, the dictator himself, "driven by violent frenzy," is distrustful
and full of fear, and is the least likely to do what he wants to do personally: "the life of the reigning dictator
is altogether wretched" (9.577c-579d).
A
wretched man is a good description of the tyrant-king Kreon. Antigone admits to
Kreon that she went against his edict; she buried her brother who had been a
traitor to the city because she believed that the gods' traditions for such
rites were infallible and therefore took precedence over Kreon's decree.
Haimon, arguing from a democratic point of view, tells Kreon what the majority
of citizens are saying in support of Antigone's actions and pleads for Kreon to
believe in the voice of the people "for once." Haimon points out that
one exposes his true emptiness if he thinks that he alone has intelligence.
Kreon stubbornly retorts: "I never surrender when I know something is
wrong" (Ant.
883-905). Earlier, the brave Sentry—one of a few who were not among the
conforming majority—pointed out Kreon's fallibility to his face: "Sir,
it's terrible; you make your mind up when even what's wrong looks right" (Ant. 403-4). The Chorus sings the curse
for every dictator: "And when he has bound the laws of this earth beside
Justice pledged to the gods, he rules his homeland; but he has no home who
recklessly marries an illegitimate cause" (Ant. 450-54). When the suicides of Antigone, Haimon, and Eurydice
are discovered, the Messenger states: "Kreon has shown there is no greater
evil than men's failure to consult and to consider" (Ant. 1436-9). The Chorus
chimes in: "For their grand schemes or bold words the proud pay with great
wounds . . ." (Ant.
1532-3).
We
can, indeed, find many cases in history that seem to support Plato's assessment
that the tyrannical soul is wretched and can cite instances where such rulers'
lives end up in personal catastrophe; Saddam Hussein comes to mind as the
archetypal despot, formally with many bodyguards, secretly moving from palace
to palace, unable to travel in the open, unable to trust anyone, and one who
loses family in war and ultimately everything, or so it seems. However, Plato's
criticism of democracy is off track. Even though it was restricted to a small
percentage of male citizens, Athens
of the fifth century B.C. seems to refute the notion that democracy necessarily
leads to an undisciplined and unworthy life. As has been discussed, those
citizens partook freely and enthusiastically in every aspect of public life,
thus enhancing the culture overall and enriching their own individual lives.
The
leaders in Athens
were wise to realize that for democracy to work the cities must remain small
enough such that the population is, as Aristotle proposed, "the largest
number which suffices for the purposes of life, and can be taken in at a single
view" (Mumford 186). In all their wisdom, though, the great minds of that
era did not understand the major shortcomings of their limited
democracy—excluding the majority of their population from the good life and
denigrating manual labor and commerce. Nevertheless, this limited democracy and
culture of fifth century Athens was far superior and conducive to human life
and toward producing harmony among the one and the many when compared to the
hive-like structured, stifling, and controlled Republic of Plato's imagination
and Kreon’s Thebes.
Mumford, Lewis. The City in History: Its Origins,
Its Transformations, and Its Prospects. San Diego: Harcourt, Inc., 1961.
Plato. Plato's Republic. Trans. G.M.A. Grube. Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing Company, 1974.
Sophocles. Antigone. Trans. Richard Emil Braun.
Ed. William Arrowsmith. New York: Oxford University
Press, 1973.
Webster, T. B. L. "Attica
and Its Population." Athenian Culture and Society, (34-57).
Reproduced in "Humanities 540" course handbook, California State
University, Dominguez Hills,
Revised November 1996 (55-67).
Title page quotes: “Correct Quotes 1.0” software. Copyright
© 1990-92. WordStar International Inc. Software
published by: WordStar International Incorporated
|