SURVIVING THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS ABOUT

PERSONAL IDENTITY QUESTIONS:

A REJECTION OF DEREK PARFIT'S MORAL THEORY

___________________

A Thesis

Presented

to the Faculty of

California State University Dominguez Hills

___________________

In Partial Fulfillment

of the Requirements for the Degree

Master of Arts

in

Humanities

­­___________________

by

Susan Fleck

Spring 2008


 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Copyright by

SUSAN FLECK

2008

All Rights Reserved

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Dedicated in loving memory to my husband, Robert E. Fleck.

The memories of his companionship, constant love, abiding friendship,

and unfailing support are forever ingrained in my heart.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

TABLE OF CONTENTS

 

 

PAGE

COPYRIGHT PAGE……………………………………………………………………..ii

APPROVAL PAGE…………………………………………………………….………..iii

DEDICATION…………………………………………………………………….……..iv

TABLE OF CONTENTS…………………………………………………………….…...v

ABSTRACT…………………………………………………………………………..…vii

CHAPTER

1.     INTRODUCTION…………………………………..…………………………..…....1

2.     IMPORTANCE OF PERSONAL IDENTITY PROBLEM………………………….4

3.     HISTORY OF THE DEBATES…………………..………………………………....10

Hobbes to Kant……………………………………………………………..……10

Contemporary Debates………………………………………………………..…16

4.     IDENTITY VERSUS SURVIVAL………………………………..………………..19

Changing the Question…….…………………………………………………….19

Shoemaker Promotes Survival………………………………………………..….20

Survival Thought Experiments…………………………………………………..21

Parfit: Survival in Degrees..…………………………………………………...…22

5.     PARFIT’S PERSONAL IDENTITY THEORY…………………………………….24

Relation R…..…………….………………….………………………………..…24

Q-Relations………………….………………………………………………..….26

Unity of Consciousness…………….……………...……………………………..29

Indeterminate Answers………………………………………………………..…33

Survival Is More Important Than Identity……………………………………….35

Do Parfit’s Puzzle Cases Convince?…………………………………………..…43

CHAPTER                                                                                                                   PAGE

6.     MORAL IMPLICATIONS OF PARFIT’S IDENTITY THEORIES:

      A MOVE FROM ETHICAL EGOISM TOWARD IMPERSONAL ALTRUISM....45

Overview.………………….…………………………………………………..…45

Contemplating One’s Demise.………………………………………………..….47

A Reductionist Look at Self-Interest……………...…………………………..…49

Impartial Altrusim…………………………………………………………..……51

Social Changes……………………………………………………………..…….51

Unity………………………………………………………………………..……56

Contrast With Other Personal Identity Theories……………………………..…..58

7.     QUESTIONING THE USE OF SCIENCE
FICTION THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS.....................................................................61

Why Thought Experiments Are Used.………………………………………...…61

How Thought Experiments Are Used ………………………………………..….63

Einstein’s Example………………...……………...…………………………..…66

More Problems With Personal Identity Thought Experiments………………..…68

Unger’s Experiments..………………………………………………………..….70

Korsgaard On Outside Influence and Pain…………………………………….....73

Drawing Conclusions From Experiments……………………………………..…74

Real Life Puzzle Cases….………………………………………………………..75

8.     CONCLUSION………………………………………………………………..…….79

WORKS CITED……………………………………………………………………..…..83

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

ABSTRACT

Derek Parfit and other philosophers put forth science fiction thought experiments to substantiate their views on personal identity, a topic that subsumes the metaphysical nature of humans and persons. The moral and ethical implications from Parfit’s account are far reaching and revolutionary. A review of the literature and debates surrounding Parfit’s views is conducted. Other methodologies for exploring the nature of personal identity are examined. The conclusion is that judgments about personal identity and survival should not be formed based solely on intuitions derived from the methodology of using imaginary thought experiments.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

CHAPTER 1

INTRODUCTION

Most people, either consciously or implicitly, have a commonsense belief that they each constitute a unified self. David Hume reflects that some philosophers think that we cannot be certain of anything if we doubt the "perfect identity and simplicity" of our own continuing existence (131).  However, based upon the numerous and diverse theories about personal identity found in the literature, one realizes that such a commonsense belief is in itself an unarticulated speculative theory. I agree with Daniel Kolak and Raymond Martin who contend that a healthy skepticism about our individual unities liberates us to create alternative theories and we may thereby come closer to the truth about ourselves. When exploring these theories, we will have enriched experiences by viewing ourselves and the world from different perspectives (Unity Introduction 15). Nevertheless, it is important to be skeptical about alternative theories: often they are the basis for promoting radical changes in one's beliefs about morality and ethical behavior.

There are many questions surrounding the general topic of personal identity. Although all of them are related, they are different questions. Eric Olson provides a summary of eight questions, stated briefly here. (1) Who am I? This is a question about one’s individual psychological identity and how this changes over time. (2) What is necessary and sufficient for something to be counted as a person? For example, can an ovum or embryo, or someone in a vegetative state be considered a person? (3) The Persistence question asks: What are the necessary and sufficient criteria for personal identity for a person to be the same person over time. This is different from the Evidence question: (4) What evidence determines whether the same person here now (say in the courtroom) is the one who was at a specific place yesterday? (5) The Population question asks: How many people are there at a certain place at a certain time?  What does that number signify? Could a human being with a split personality be considered two persons? (6) What am I, metaphysically speaking? Am I merely a biological animal, or essentially an immaterial soul, or bundles of perceptions, or the bearer of a historical narrative, or some combination of these things? (7) How could I have been different than I actually am, say if I had different parents? (8) What is important about the fact of my identity or my persistence? Can survival be separated from identity and can that be more important? (Olson)

The problem of personal identity that is the focus of this paper is essentially the persistence question of what makes someone the same, continuously existing person over time. In order to answer that question, one must delve into the question about what is the nature of persons. The question of survival versus identity will be discussed at length in relation to the persistence question. With the added dimension of consciousness, and in particular self-consciousness, the problem of trying to account for unity and multiplicity over time makes personal identity a special case in trying to establish the metaphysical principles that determine the ways one establishes boundaries of entities and counts how many things there are. Tamar Gendler reports that most recent philosophical literature on this subject is based on arguments that "use an assumed convergence of response" to imaginary cases, or thought experiments (448). Kathleen Wilkes backs up this opinion. She claims that the literature on personal identity is "rich and fun" because the majority of it focuses on thought experiments that "amuse, provoke the imagination, and allow one to reach splendidly revolutionary conclusions" (1).

Derek Parfit and other philosophers put forth thought experiments, to postulate that one's survival is more important than one's identity. Parfit’s arguments to make this case are put forth later. The moral and ethical implications from this perspective are far reaching and revolutionary. Before subscribing to any proposition put forward in the arena of personal identity, one must proceed with caution and evaluate the philosopher's logic and the methodology used to support his arguments. Because he is influential in the debates about personal identity, I focus on Parfit's theories and method of analysis.

To further an investigation about the nature of personal identity, I address these four questions of interest in this order: (1) Why is the topic of personal identity important? (2) Is survival more important than identity? (3) What are the moral and ethical implications of Parfit's personal identity theories? (4) Is the use of imaginary thought experiments a valid or successful method for exploring this topic?

These conclusions will be demonstrated: (1) Survival is not more important than identity because one's survival cannot be separated from one's identity. (2) Parfit's logic in this arena is flawed and his methodology is at the heart of what is wrong with his theories. (3) The use of science fiction thought experiments is not valid as the primary method for answering personal identity questions. (4) Based on these findings, fundamental changes in current moral theory must not come about in the way Parfit and others in a similar manner advocate. Heeding my own advice I thus proceed with caution.                        

CHAPTER 2

IMPORTANCE OF PERSONAL IDENTITY PROBLEM

Why are issues of personal identity important? Investigations within different fields of study are examining the questions of personal identity. The topic is still very much alive and heavily debated in our contemporary world. This section describes areas of investigation about personal identity within the areas of psychology, metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics. First there is a brief discussion about unity of consciousness from a psychological perspective and then an example of an experiment examining how one may form a concept of one's self-worth and how that may relate to personal identity. Next, an example is given about how the nature of persons is explored in the realm of physics. Then it will be shown how one philosopher ties the metaphysical problem of free will to our subject problem. Following that, there is a brief glimpse regarding how personal identity, according to one view, is deeply connected with epistemology. Finally, there is a discussion about how important personal identity theory is in relationship to moral and ethical theories. One could argue that one's belief about personal identity is implicit in whatever moral and ethical theories that one adopts.

On the psychological front, evidence from experiments using patients who have had commissurotomies[1] (so-called split-brain patients) and from investigations about Multiple Personality Disorder patients suggest a threat to the commonsense view about one's unity of consciousness. As Jennifer Radden points out, a claim that one body may have more than one center of awareness affects how we would understand selves and minds and how we would understand the concepts of awareness and subjectivity (347).  In another psychological experiment, job applicants conceptualized their own self-worth differently depending upon what other kinds of people were in the waiting room with them. Based on these findings, Kenneth Gergen suggests "that personal identity is an important measure dependent on the immediate or continuing social milieu. . . . What is "truth" about self depends on those available for comparison" (379-80).

Within the world of physics and neurophysiology, scientists are trying to understand the quantum mechanics of the brain. Allen Stairs reports that many have used quantum mechanics to provide arguments for various theories about selves such as splitting and re-merging selves and mind-body dualism (453). He poses the question: "What does supervenience[2] tell us about the superposition of mental states, or more broadly, of states of the self?" (466). He concludes that at this point of such investigations we do not have any understanding of this phenomena and, thus, "the relationship between mind and microphysics is still a mystery" (467).

Within the more abstract world of philosophy, Christine Korsgaard describes the connection between the problem of personal identity and the problem of free will. Although these are both metaphysical concepts that effect matters of ethics, Korsgaard thinks that it is more important to consider them as related in finding expression in one's identification with a unifying principle underlying one's way of choosing. We adopt an identification from a deliberative standpoint not because of any metaphysical facts; rather, it is because of the necessity of making deliberative choices.  Whether or not philosophy is able to answer the metaphysical questions of personal identity, Korsgaard reflects: "I must still decide whether the consideration that some future person is ‘me’ has some special normative force for me. It is practical reason that requires me to construct an identity for myself: whether metaphysics is a guide to me in this or not is an open question" (325).

It can be seen that Korsgaard subscribes to Kantian ethics. Louis Sass considers the implication of conceiving of subjectivity along Kantian transcendental terms, "as the medium by which everything is known or in which it has its being." If that is true, then Sass asks how it could ever be possible for subjectivity itself to be known. Subjectivity could not become an object within the medium that it itself is. Furthermore, if human consciousness is viewed as the foundation for all of reality that is relevant to human beings, then the implication is that "consciousness, or the human self, might seem to hold a position of ultimate sovereignty and omniscience" (325).

These are but a few examples of various inquiries and debates regarding the issues of personal identity. The most important reason for investigating the problem of personal identity involves ethical concerns. David Shoemaker asks a provocative question about whether metaphysical questions regarding personal identity should be prior to the ethics entailed in proposed answers, or whether, instead, the metaphysics should be constrained by our practices of moral responsibility. He informs that Kantians  and communitarians argue against the disunifying implications from reductionist accounts like Parfit’s. Instead, they declare that the human community is unified either as practical agents or as selves dependent on social matrices and that we are in a moral space together for normative reasons. Any identities to be constructed on these accounts must be constrained by such normative considerations (D. Shoemaker). However, if the current standard methodology of putting metaphysics first were to be abandoned, there would be much debate about which ethical system should be chosen. In any case, most seem to be in agreement regarding the important relationship between personal identity and ethics. We still have good reason to maintain that ethics depends on the metaphysics.

John Locke articulates: "In this personal identity is founded all the right and justice of reward and punishment; happiness and misery being that for which every one is concerned for himself, and not mattering what becomes of any substance not joined to, or affected with that consciousness” (120). Locke claimed that person is what we call our self as a continuing, same intelligent agent, and that it is a forensic term that applies to one’s actions and their merit. As individuals, one must think that there is something that constitutes one's self that one would have a concern for, something that has had a continued duration and will have such duration for whatever future length of one's life is to come (121-2). This thinking is the foundation for one of the dominant theories in ethics, that of self-interest. Following is Parfit’s formulation of the Self-interest Theory:

This claims that, for each person, there is one supremely rational ultimate aim: that things go as well as possible for himself. A rational agent should both have, and be ultimately governed by, a temporally neutral bias in his own favour. It is irrational for anyone to do what he believes will be worse for himself. (“Personal Identity, Rationality” 301)

Parfit declares his agenda to refute the Self-interest Theory by targeting two commonly held beliefs. The first belief he tackles is about the nature of personal identity that holds that in all cases the question about identity must be determinate. With this view, one must be able to definitively know whether one would exist or not given any scenario of future events. The second commonly held belief is that if the question about identity is indeterminate, then we are unable to answer related important questions such as those about survival, memory, and responsibility (“Personal Identity” 167). Parfit asserts that he will convince us to change our view about the nature of personal identity and that this should persuade us "to change our beliefs about rationality, and about morality" (“Psychological View” 261). It will become apparent in the course of this discussion that this author is not swayed by Parfit's propositions. Problems with his logic and his use of thought experiments will be pointed out.

Thomas Reid declares: "But identity, when applied to persons, has no ambiguity, and admits not of degrees, or of more and less. It is the foundation of all rights and obligations, and of all accountableness; and the notion of it is fixed and precise" (126-27). If it is true that the notion of personal identity is fixed and precise, then I would have no reasons for investigating the topic and for writing this thesis. However, as theories abound in this arena, one can see that there is still plenty of controversy to chew upon. Nevertheless, as John Pickering reminds us, a fundamental assumption in social science, law and theology is the notion of the enduring identity of individual persons to which legal and moral responsibility can be attached. He ponders the implications of the possibility that philosophy would discover that the enduring self is an erroneous notion. What kind of impact would such a finding have on our legal and moral institutions? One option would be to put philosophy aside and continue to treat persons in the same manner as per our current customs and practices. "But philosophical inquiry," Pickering muses, "happily, resists being set aside as much as it resists ethical neutrality. Moreover, the deeper the inquiry, the more significant it eventually appears to be" (74-75).

So, one realizes that much is at stake in pursuing investigations about the nature of personal identity. If philosophers are able to persuasively argue that the enduring identity of individual persons is not important or possibly not even a valid assumption, then the moral fabric of our society may begin to unravel and be knitted anew with different assumptions. It will be shown that Parfit is one who calls for revolutionary changes in society’s moral values based upon this kind of argument. Following a historical overview about the problem of personal identity, the discussion will focus upon Parfit’s arguments. He argues that the nature of personal identity does not necessarily need to be determinate and, furthermore, that one's survival is more important than one's identity.

CHAPTER  3

HISTORY OF THE DEBATES
Hobbes to Kant

Before examining Parfit's arguments, a historical background is provided as context for the commonly held beliefs that Parfit wants to undermine. How did the problem of personal identity become one of the central concerns of philosophy?  Thomas Hobbes was one of the first to distinguish this problem from the more general problem of identity per se. He explains the three dominant views about the identity of things, about what makes a thing the same thing at later time. Individuality is based upon matter, or form, or an "aggregate of all the accidents together."  He clarifies: "For form, that when a man is grown from an infant to be an old man, though his matter be changed, yet he is still the same numerical man; for that identity, which cannot be attributed to the matter, ought probably to be ascribed to the form" (111).

What might this form of a person consist of? When Renι Descartes came to the conclusion that he could not doubt his conscious existence because any act of doubting presupposes consciousness, this begged the question, what is it that exists?  Jonathan Shear reminds us that "Descartes concluded that the self that we know indubitably exists is a consciousness, the selfsame consciousness, single, simple and continuing throughout one's awareness" (Descartes  66 ff., 121; Shear, “Experiential” 407-8). Parfit tells us that one of the current prevailing views about what persons are and what is involved in their personal identity is known as the Cartesian view, a view that espouses that a person is essentially a non-physical substance, or soul. The current form of this view has evolved away from Descartes’ theory that our soul is seated somewhere in the body or brain, for example, in the pineal gland. It is now often called the Ego Theory, or transcendental view, whereby a person continues to exist as an Ego, a subject of experience. According to this view, a person's multiple experiences at any one time are unified in consciousness because one ego-person is having these perceptions and experiences. A whole life is unified because one ego-person has all of those life-long experiences: one ego-person is one and the same subject of experiences (“Divided Minds” 83-84).

According to Amihud Gilead, Baruch Spinoza criticizes Descartes for separating mind from body and for claiming that the mind’s self-knowledge is self-evident. Spinoza assumes that we cannot have immediate awareness of our personal identity. “The mind does not know itself unless in so far as it perceives the ideas of the affections of the body” (“Ethics” II, Prop. XXIII qtd. in Gilead). For Spinoza, the mind can only know itself through the cognition of the active or passive body. Gilead interprets: “. . . the mind gets acquainted with its own identity and unity by investigating its place in the causal chain . . . as a body which has a certain ratio of movement and rest.”  In order to understand anything, one must be able to fit its idea into “a network which reflects a complete chain of causes and effects” (Gilead). As I understand Gilead’s reading of Spinoza, personal identity would consist of one understanding one’s place, or one’s impression, in the whole causal chain which constitutes the monistic Reality.

Martin Lin points out that some have interpreted Spinoza to have preceded Locke by twenty years in fixing the memory criterion of personal identity. In his “Ethics,” Spinoza gave an amnesia example similar to cases that led Locke to make a distinction among persons, human beings, and souls. Spinoza had heard about a Spanish poet who did not believe that he had authored the stories and tragedies that he had in fact written. Spinoza judged: “He might have been taken for a grown-up infant had he also forgotten his native tongue” (IV39S qtd. in Lin). Lin explains that Spinoza shared Locke’s intuition that memory loss indicates significant discontinuity, but Spinoza did not distinguish between the body and the mind. Nevertheless, he concluded that in the poet’s case the same human being did not survive his disease. Lin proceeds to explain Spinoza’s theories about complex bodies and memory and how the poet’s case can be interpreted to be about personal identity. With Spinoza, severe memory loss follows an overall change in ratio of the total complex structure of a human: normal discontinuity, or forgetfulness, does not indicate this change. With this view, a person’s same physical ratio must remain intact for survival, or persistence, and not merely psychological continuity and connectedness via memory (Lin).

Gottfried Leibniz also appreciated the importance of memory in distinguishing the nature of humans from that of other animals. In his “Monadology,” Leibniz criticized the Cartesians because that they believe that minds alone are monads and that beasts do not have souls (14). However, he thinks that it would be more appropriate to give substances that have perception only the name “monad” or “entelechy,” and the name “soul” should be reserved when perception is accompanied by memory (19). He tells us that the soul is more than a simple monad, and that memory imitates reason, providing the soul with a kind of succession. Thus, for example, dogs have souls because they remember pain that a stick has caused and run away when the stick is shown to them (20; 26). However, he claims that through “knowledge of necessary and eternal truths” men acquire reason and the sciences, “raising us to the knowledge of ourselves and of God. And it is this in us that is called the rational soul or mind” (29). It is through these truths that we are able to conceptualize and make abstractions such that “we rise to reflective acts, which make us think of what is called I . . .” (30). So for Leibniz, although memory is important to underpin persistence of the soul, personal identity is the result of rational thinking, but from a different process than what Descartes proclaimed.

Locke tried to eliminate an immaterial substance from an account of personal identity, according to Kolak and Martin, by arguing that sameness of consciousness is what makes someone the same person throughout their life. Although he still clung to a form of a substance view, he originated the important relational view: Personal identity consists in relations among transient elements. "The important relations, on his view, are those that obtain among present conscious memories and the earlier experiences or actions remembered" (“Personal Identity” 164). Locke was the first thinker to use thought experiments in dealing with the personal identity problem and the first to explicitly connect personal identity with ethical concerns. He has been called the father of the personal identity problem, because for a long time most thinkers who wrote on this subject were responding to Locke (D. Shoemaker).

Joseph Butler and Reid took exception to having personal identity become separated from both biological and substance-soul identity. Butler called Locke’s notion a “wonderful mistake” because Locke failed to recognize the circularity of his thoughts. Consciousness-memory presupposes identity and therefore cannot constitute it. A memory of an experience is not what makes it mine: I am able to remember it because it is already mine. Butler’s view is that these are experiences of a substance that constitutes me now. Reid agrees and poses two more objections (D. Shoemaker).

For the first challenge, Reid uses an example of a brave officer who at age forty, as he is stealing an enemy’s standard, remembers stealing an apple at age ten. However, when he was eighty, he remembers stealing the standard, but no longer remembers stealing the apple. According to Locke’s view, the old man would both be and not be identical to the apple-stealer. He would be identical to the apple-stealer because of the transitivity of the identity relation: he is identical to the officer, who is himself identical to the apple-stealer. But he would not be identical to the apple-stealer because he has no direct memory of that boy’s experiences. Secondly, Reid asks how identity, i.e., sameness, could be based on the relation of consciousness, something that changes from moment to moment. On this basis, no one could be held responsible for one’s actions. This also upsets the normative consideration of prudence: if one changes from day to day, why should one care what did happen to one yesterday, or what might happen to one tomorrow? Because of these absurd implications, Reid rejects Locke’s notion of personal identity, and commits himself to the view that one’s identity is “fixed and precise” (D. Shoemaker). It will be explained later how contemporary thinkers meet these challenges posed by Butler and Reid.

David Hume’s view of the self is about as far away from being fixed and precise as one can get. One might say that Hume is the father of logical construction theories for personal identity. In contrast with the Cartesian view of a substantial self, Hume offers the Bundle view which accounts for our concept of self, according to Shear, in terms of bundles of experiences that are connected by the logical relationships of contiguity and resemblances of our perceptions (“Experiential” 408). On Hume's view, one mistakes what is merely a bundle of perceptions for a self as a perceiver. Parfit expresses: "A Bundle Theorist knows that it is absurd to think of one's self or others as merely series of events. On the other hand, according to this view, there are persons or subjects only in a language-dependent way” (“Divided Minds” 83-84). Kolak and Martin think that this poses a dilemma for Hume: "It seems an outright contradiction for you to discover that you do not exist" (“Personal Identity” 167-8). However, this is a dilemma for all philosophers working on the problem: To what may you refer? That question is the personal identity problem in a nutshell.

Immanuel Kant responded to Hume, as Kolak and Martin explain, by asserting that one's experiences are unified and that unified experiences cannot exist unowned.  Having experiences, therefore, presupposes an experiencer. However, someone who has experiences is not a substantial self (“Personal Identity” 167). He agreed with Descartes, as Shear suggests, in that inner experience is extended in time, and outer experience is extended in space as well as in time. If an experience did not have these spatio-temporal qualities, they would be too short or too small to be seen. On the other hand Kant agreed with Hume in that one could not derive an overall principle of unity, or any definite concept of a necessarily inferred unitary self, from the content of one's experiences. Instead, Kant called such an overall unity "the transcendental unity of apperception.” The self, according to Kant, can only be known as an abstraction, a "something=X." Because both Descartes and Hume were right in that the self is both absolutely necessary and at the same time vacuous and ungraspable, Kant muses that this paradox "mocks and torments" men (Kant 329 ff.; Shear “Experiential” 408-9).

Although there were certainly philosophers and thinkers after Kant and before the late twentieth century that discussed the human condition and human nature per se, I have not read or seen any essays from this era particularly addressing the personal identity problem. That is not to say that there are none. But whenever I have seen a collection of essays on this topic, they usually include some of the aforementioned thinkers and then the contemporary philosophers working on this problem.

 

Contemporary Debates

Modern philosophers are still wrestling with the problem of personal identity. Kolak and Martin explain that even though Kant's theory of a transcendental self still has influence, it accounts for personal identity by appealing to such substances which focuses such an inquiry outside the bounds of both experience and science. Contemporary theorists usually work within the context of relational views (“Personal Identity” 168). Martin maintains, as David Shoemaker tells us, that Locke was the first one to provide us with a fission thought experiment when he proposed a finger gaining a separate consciousness from the rest of a person’s body. However, Locke did not clarify what the relations were between the finger and the fingerless person still in existence. Shoemaker suggests that if Locke would have loosened his account of identity in order to admit a relationship of degrees in consciousness to allow for limited recall the further one gets from experiences, this may have then enabled an admission of degrees into the normative arena. Shoemaker further speculates that if  Locke would have considered a case of consciousness of one person duplicated in two different bodies, and then discussed what this might mean in terms of identity, relationships, and normativity, then he would have begun to work on the questions that are “at the heart of the contemporary approach” (D. Shoemaker).

These theorists use complex types of memory and psychological relationships in their neo-Humean theories about personal identity. Nevertheless, as will be explained, reductionist accounts of identity is still Lockean in that personal identity consists in overlapping chains of continuity and psychological connectedness that hold strongly from a day to day basis. They have expanded the Lockean criterion of memory to include other relations such as intentions and desires. The contemporary debates began with Parfit’s early 1970s articles and his subsequent restatement and development of these ideas in Part III of his book Reasons and Persons.

Before delving into the specifics of Parfit’s and others’ thought experiments and views, this historical overview will conclude with a general explanation of the three main contemporary camps and by naming some of the workers in these camps. Eric Olson provides a good summary of this information. Proposed solutions to the Persistence Question fall into one of three categories, or type of criterion necessary for personal identity to obtain. With the Psychological Approach, you are the future being that inherits its mental features such as memories, beliefs, desires, and so forth, from you, and you are that past being whose mental features you inherited. There is dispute about whether these mental features must be underpinned by physical continuity, or whether a “non-branching” requirement is necessary (branching will be explained later). Since the early twentieth century, most philosophers writing in this arena subscribe to some version of the psychological criterion. Advocates of this approach include Mark Johnston, Brian Garrett, H. Hudson, David Lewis, Thomas Nagel, Derek Parfit, John Perry, Sydney Shoemaker, and Peter Unger (Olson).

Olson calls the second camp the Somatic Approach: some “brute physical relation” is required through time for identity to obtain. Whether or not you survive has nothing to do with psychological facts: rather, your body must survive. (This should not be confused with the Evidence Question that deals with finding out who is who.) Even though Olson himself holds this position, he admits that it is an unpopular one. Other advocates in this camp are M. Ayers, W. R. Carter, D. Mackie, P. van Inwagen, and Bernard Williams (Olson).

With the psychological and somatic approach, something, either bodily or mental continuity, is necessary for personal identity to persist through time: something other than itself. The third view, called the Simple View, denies this. This view is often combined, but not necessarily, with the notion that we are immaterial (with souls) and have no parts. With this view, Olson claims: “The only correct and complete answer to the Persistence Question is that a person existing at one time is identical with a being existing at another if and only if they are identical.” Those writing in this camp include R. Chisholm, R. Swinburne, E.J. Lowe, and T. Merricks (Olson). This view is sometimes referred to as the Ego, or soul view.

CHAPTER 4

IDENTITY VERSUS SURVIVAL

Changing the Question

One major contemporary view is centered on Parfit's reductionist account. As it has been mentioned, the contemporary debates on the Persistence Question began with Parfit’s initial essays on this subject. It will be explained later how his account is based upon reductionism. Parfit sets the stage for changing the debate by changing one of the central questions. The persistence question asks: under what condition is your personal identity preserved? Parfit focuses on this question: under what conditions is what matters primarily to you in survival preserved? Until recently, philosophers thought that these two questions would produce the same answer, i.e., that identity is what matters the most in survival. However, in the late twentieth century, philosophers began to argue that there were more important things than identity per se. The importance of personal identity was called into question through the use of thought experiments involving hypothetical fission cases in which one person splits into two qualitatively identical persons—persons who are also qualitatively identical to the original person (Martin, “Identity” 291).

In this section two thought experiment examples are presented that Sydney Shoemaker uses to argue for the priority of survival over identity. Next, an explanation is provided about how philosophers use thought experiments in their arguments to support the conclusion that survival matters more than personal identity. Then, there is an examination of Parfit's analyses in support of his thesis that survival is more important than identity. The conclusion is that Parfit has not made a good case. Finally, a summary is given about why survival should not be separated from identity: therefore, it is not more important than identity.

 

Shoemaker Promotes Survival

Sydney Shoemaker questions the assumption that what a person wants in wishing to survive is that the same person who wants to survive will exist in the future after any survival event in question. He subscribes to a priority of survival over identity based upon conclusions from using thought experiments. For example, if I were given two options for having my healthy half-brain transplanted into another body that is healthy, I should choose the less risky procedure whereby my cancer ridden half-brain and body would be destroyed after the operation. With this option, it would mean for certain that my identity will not carry forward onto the recipient person even though there is psychological continuity between me and the recipient. Two persons cannot have the same identity at one time. The more risky process entails first destroying my diseased half-brain, and then transplanting the other half. If that procedure were chosen, the recipient person would have no "competitor" at any time for the status of being me, and therefore, she could count as me. The reason I should choose the less risky procedure is because, in a case like this, my identity is not important, but survival is important (271). 

Shoemaker then describes the fission case (also called the My Division case) where both of my healthy half-brains are transplanted successfully into two other bodies. Even if I accept the analysis that neither recipient person will be me, nevertheless, before the surgery I should not consider this procedure as impending death. Instead, assuming that the psychological continuity criteria of personal identity is a correct view, I should have an attitude toward my two successor persons essentially like I would normally have about my own future delights, successes, and failures under normal circumstances (272).

 

Survival Thought Experiments

Peter Unger demonstrates how philosophers employ thought experiments in three different manners to describe what matters in survival. With what he calls the desirability use one would describe what would make continued survival more desirable than death. With the second, the prudential use, one looks at survival from the perspective of what future being is there that one would rationally be intrinsically connected to. For example, suppose you must undergo an irreversible operation whereby your memories are eradicated and you will end up with an IQ of about thirty. According to the desirability use, the answer to the question about how much of what matters in survival will there be after this kind of surgery will be: not much—this would be about as bad as death. With this view, you may want to arrange for a painless death after the surgery, even if you considered the person emerging from the operation to be yourself. However, with the prudential view, you would question whether there was someone left from the surgery for whom you had a rational egoistic concern. You would answer: "Yes; there is someone left, namely, the unfortunate amnesiac imbecile who will be you: and, for yourself, the strength of the rational self-centered concern will be very great" (196-8).

The third manner Unger describes is the constitutive use. With this method, one focuses on what factors about a case counts toward a case involving someone who survives. In these types of cases there are factors constituting survival that are matters of degree. This use, unlike the other two, does not involve evaluative or motivational aspects concerning one's survival. Therefore, Unger thinks, this use has no direct connection with self interest, or "rational concern for one's self in the future" (198). The constitutive use of survival thought experiments is the method that Parfit employs in his attempt to bring down the Self-interest Theory of ethics.

 

Parfit: Survival in Degrees

Josι Bermϊdez describes the first prong in Parfit's overall strategy, within his psychophysical reductionist philosophical viewpoint, which is to promote the importance of survival over personal identity:

It starts with a version of the general ontological principle that there is no entity without identity, interprets this so that it is satisfied only if there is always a determinate answer to the question of whether the putative entity has continued or ceased to exist, and then deploys thought experiments and sorites form of argument to show that cases can be imagined where there is no such determinate answer. (433)

The neo-Humean theories of Parfit, as Radden reports, give us a scalar conception of personal identity whereby a later self may be identical with an earlier one by some lesser degree. This eliminates the presumption that there can only be one person to one bodily lifetime (344). Based on cases he presents, Parfit claims that we should change our view about our nature, which will, in turn, change our view about how we should behave as humans. He stresses the strong relationship between these themes in quoting Rawls, who said that “the correct regulative principle for anything depends upon the nature of that thing” (qtd. in Parfit, Reasons 336). Let us now look at how Parfit comes to his conclusions about the nature of persons, and why survival is more important than personal identity with his view.

Parfit thinks that if there was empirical evidence supporting the claims of reincarnation, then this would be good evidence supporting the Cartesian, or Ego View, of the nature of persons and personal identity. If it was discovered that there is no physical continuity between a past life and a current life, but the present person has a way of knowing about the past life which is like a memory of the present life, then we might abandon the belief that “the carrier of memory is the brain. . . . This would not, however, show that the continued existence of these Egos is all-or-nothing” (Reasons 227). Parfit claims that we do not have good evidence for reincarnation, or any other evidence to support the Cartesian Ego. Therefore, we have reason to reject this view (Reasons 228). However, given the numerous books and articles that claim to provide true and real accounts of past lives of persons now living, one may ask: why is a supposition of reincarnation more far-fetched than some of the puzzle cases that Parfit uses as arguments to support his claims? Albeit, there is a distinction between a positive truth claim about reincarnation and the use of thought experiments.  Nevertheless, since he cites the possibility of reincarnation as a plausible argument for the Ego view of identity, it would be helpful if Parfit discussed what kinds of evidence would count as verifying claims of past lives.

CHAPTER 5

PARFIT’S PERSONAL IDENTITY THEORY

Relation R

How does Parfit attempt to refute the Ego view? What view of personal identity does he hold? Although Parfit maintains a strict physical view of personal identity, he gives us a modified version of what he thinks are the necessary and sufficient conditions for personal identity to obtain: “[. . .] to be a person, a being must be self-conscious, aware of its identity and its continued existence over time.” His reductionist view is that “personal identity just consists in physical and psychological continuity” (“Psychological View” 229). He presumes that mere identity stripped of continuity would paralyze a person. One could not act, plan, or think without connections of memory and intentions (“Psychological View” 230-32). One wonders where someone with an advanced form of Alzheimer's disease or with severe mental retardation would fit into Parfit's scheme. This begs the question: in Parfit’s account, how much psychological continuity over what length of time qualifies one to be considered a person, as distinguished from merely being human? One could argue that there is the problem of a matter of degree of severity of Alzheimer’s disease or retardation such that one could not establish an arbitrary cutoff point by which humans on one side of the line would satisfy Parfit’s conditions for personal identity. This quandary fits into the later discussion about Parfit’s argument that survival is a matter of degrees.

Parfit revises Locke’s memory-consciousness concept such that when we have an “overlapping chain of experience-memories,” then there is a continuity of memory. For example, most of us can remember some of our experiences of the previous day. Therefore, from day to day we have this continuity. Besides memories, there are other venues for psychological continuity such as intentions, beliefs, and desires. We may have thousands of direct psychological connections between who we are today (X) and who we were yesterday (Y). But there may only be a few connections between who we are today and who we were twenty years ago. It is the overlapping chains concept that Parfit uses to tie all these together to count for a continuous person. His expanded Lockean view gives us the Psychological Criterion, or deep psychological connectedness (hereafter called Relation R) (“Psychological View” 232).

There are three versions of this criterion based on what is the right kind of cause of continuity: the Narrow version stipulates that it must be the normal cause, it can be any reliable cause with the Wide version, and any cause under the Widest version (“Psychological View” 232). Using Parfit’s simple Teletransportation example, let us say that I enter a teletransporter whereby my body and brain are exactly replicated on Mars out of new material and my original body and brain are destroyed. Under the Narrow version, the replica on Mars would not be me because the continuance was not due to a normal cause. It would be me, however, under the two Wide formulae. He uses the following analogy for accepting the wider causes in terms of psychological continuity. If scientists perfect the technology to develop artificial eyes such that a blind person could have visual experiences just like those who are not blind, then that person would still be seeing things even though the cause of sight was not normal (“Psychological View” 233). Along these lines of thinking, then, why should it matter whether this brain and body gets to Mars. The natural fear, Parfit construes, is that, according to most peoples’ belief, only that condition within a Narrow cause will ensure that I get to Mars (“Psychological View” 263).

Parfit must make a case to cause people to accept his Wide versions of personal identity theory: that it is the effect that matters, not the cause of continuity. He reminds us that Bishop Butler contends that Locke’s account of personal identity was derived from a circular argument in that one's identity consists of one’s consciousness of memories of past experiences. Butler points out that a consciousness of personal identity presupposes personal identity and therefore it cannot be a truth that it presupposes (“Psychological View” 235). Parfit admits that it is a logical truth that we can only remember our own experiences. In order to get around this logical truth and Butler’s objection, Parfit expands Locke’s view to include the continuity of memory and what he calls Relation R that includes other kinds of psychological continuity (“Personal Identity” 171).

 

Q-Relations

Parfit develops a wider relational theory of personal identity using concepts called q, or quasi-relationships. He gives us this definition of quasi-memory: “I have an accurate quasi–memory of a past experience if (1) I seem to remember having an experience, (2) someone did have this experience, and (3) my apparent memory is causally dependent, in the right kind of way, on that past experience” (“Psychological View” 235). On this account, our ordinary memories of past events become a sub-class of quasi-memories. Even though we do not quasi-remember others’ experiences, we might be able to do so if science could find a way to create a copy of another’s memory-trace within one’s brain. Furthermore, the continuity of quasi-memory is produced from overlapping strands of strong connectedness. With these expanded concepts of memory and continuity, Parfit thinks he has met Butler’s challenge. He now reduces his criteria for personal identity in claiming “that personal identity just consists in the holding of Relation R” (“Psychological View” 236-237).

Parfit provides an example by using a thought experiment. Imagine a case of Divided Brains (also called My Division), where there would be three people in an accident. One has a body destroyed but still has a healthy brain, the other two have healthy bodies but their brains are destroyed. The one person’s healthy brain is halved and then transplanted into the two other healthy human bodies.  The resultant two people would have to acknowledge that, right after such an operation, they have only q-memories of the third person whose half brain they now each possess. In a like manner, right after the surgery, they would have only the q-intentions and other such psychological attributes of that third person (“Personal Identity” 171-2). We can imagine a case like this, Parfit claims, because it is factually true that one brain hemisphere is enough for survival. He bases this assumption on stroke and other brain injury cases where one loses the function of one hemisphere. He admits that he assumes that both hemispheres have a full range of abilities (“Psychological View” 252-3). 

This assumption goes too far. According to a TV KPBS special documentary about the brain, the two hemispheres definitely do not have equal abilities and functions.[3] That technical problem aside, we still have an identity problem. Assuming that Relation R is the necessary and sufficient criterion for personal identity, we cannot claim that the resultant two people are one-and-the-same continuing original person of any of the three victims. Parfit does stipulate that personal identity cannot obtain when the psychological criterion takes a branching form, as it does in a case like this where there are two or more resultant persons with the same psychological continuity.

Furthermore, Nathan Oaklander points out that Parfit’s analysis still remains circular if one's q-memory is of one's own past experience if and only if there are numerous other q-memories of one's own earlier experiences. If he avoids circularity by saying there is strong-connectedness such that the q-memory is of one's past experience if and only if there are numerous other q-memories, then his analysis is incomplete since there could be strong-connectedness without there being any personal identity involved. Oaklander thinks that strong-connectedness is sufficient “only if all the simultaneous q-remembered experiences belong to the same person.” Parfit can apply his q-memory theory as an impersonal (non-circular) description of personal identity only if he can explain the unity of consciousness, i.e., what unifies simultaneous experiences into one and the same person (526-7).

 

Unity of Consciousness

Parfit attempts to meet this challenge, but his response is fraught with difficulties.  Unity of Consciousness seems to be the best concept that fits the “Further Fact” that many Non-Reductionists subscribe to for personal identity. However, Reductionists, according to Parfit, have a different view of unity of consciousness from that of Non-Reductionists. He explains a common understanding of unity of consciousness as being what unites different experiences one has concurrently, experiences such as me-at-this-time being aware of typing this sentence, of the sunlight streaming through the window, and of the warmth of the fire next to me. It is the fact that these are all experiences being had by me, a particular person, and that I am the subject of these experiences. Some think that what constitutes my whole life, what unites all of my experiences, thoughts, and so forth, is the fact that they are all mine. This view is that psychological unity is explained by ownership (Reasons 214-15).

Parfit claims that we cannot explain these unities by claiming the experiences are had by the same person. “These unities must be explained by describing the relations between these many experiences, and their relations to this person’s brain.  We can refer to these experiences, and fully describe the relations between them, without claiming that these experiences are had by a person” (Reasons 217). He thinks that at any one time there is in the brain a single state of awareness of simultaneous experiences, i.e., that several experiences can be the objects of one state of awareness (Reasons 250-51). At any given time, for Reductionists, nothing more is involved in unity of consciousness.

Parfit thinks he has empirical evidence backing his claims about the nature of the unity of consciousness. He points to actual cases where surgeons have performed commissurotomies by cutting the fibers connecting the two upper hemispheres of the brain in order to reduce the severity of fits of epileptic patients. A side effect of the operation, according to one surgeon, was the creation of “two separate spheres of consciousness.” Parfit goes on to describe some complications within these actual cases. For example, speech is entirely controlled by the right-handed hemisphere. Nevertheless, he denies "the necessary unity of consciousness" based on these cases whereby he thinks each hemisphere “separately displays unity of consciousness” (Reasons 245; 247). 

Recall the My Division case whereby surgeons divide my brain in half and replace each of my identical triplet sister’s destroyed brain with one of my half brains. Parfit discloses how much weight he gives to a denial of unity of consciousness:

Does it matter if, for this reason, this imagined case of complete division will always remain impossible? Given the aims of my discussion, this does not matter. This impossibility is merely technical. The one feature of the case that might be held to be deeply impossible - the division of a person’s consciousness into two separate streams - is the feature that has actually happened. It would have been important if this had been impossible, since this might have supported some claim about what we really are. It might have supported the claim that we are indivisible Cartesian Egos. It therefore matters that the division of a person’s consciousness is in fact possible. . . . the main conclusion to be drawn is that personal identity is not what matters. (Reasons 255)

Using evidence from commissurotomy patients, Parfit thinks that this suggests that the subject of our mental life is a divisible brain. Using the My Division thought experiment, Parfit declares the brain as an unfit bearer of personal identity (“Divided Minds” 88). Because Parfit puts so much weight on the importance of empirical evidence to support his theory, this warrants close scrutiny. Parfit acknowledges that he has to make many assumptions to make My Division work, such as: (1) both hemispheres have full range of capabilities, (2) it is possible to connect the nerves, and (3) the lower brain stem is either not important, or else it can also be divided. He admits that this case will probably never be possible, but, the mere technical difficulties do not matter to him. What is important to keep in mind for Parfit is that the feature whereby a person's consciousness has been divided into two separate streams has actually happened. He bolsters his argument with the fact that one can survive even if half of one's brain is destroyed or removed (“Psychological View” 253; 256).

However, R. W. Sperry explains that splitting a brain in half does not mean that each of its functional properties is divided in half. Although there is extensive bilateral redundancy and most functions seem to be fully organized on both sides, Sperry cautions against thinking that these commissurotomy patients are just as well off, or better off, mentally than before the operation. He also judges that there are other unifying factors between the two brain hemispheres that enhance normal behavior under ordinary circumstances (60-62). Wilkes points out that only half of the brain cortex is removed in hemispherectomies, not a whole half-brain. Only parts of the cortex are divided in a commissurotomy. In each case, areas that are crucial to psychological functions, the subcortical regions, are left intact. She cites neuropsychologist S. Dimond in claiming that the peripheral structures of the brain, when viewed from a perspective from within the brain, are in some sense more important than the cerebral cortex: these subcortical regions can be likened to "the display facilities of an operations room" (Wilkes 37-8).

John Robinson presents two major problems about Parfit’s denial that unity of consciousness may be a further fact. First, in cases where patients survive when one of their upper brain hemispheres is removed, there is the remaining brain stem to consider.  What psychological abilities and capacities are involved with the brain stem? Only if we could transplant an upper hemisphere into a body which already had a brain stem in it could there be a resulting person. The second problem deals with the controversial conclusion that in the cases where epileptic patients have brain nerve bundles severed there truly are two separate streams of consciousness (324-26). Robinson cites C. Trevarthen, whose more recent experimental work refutes Parfit’s conclusion: “These two way links of hemispheres with the brain stem . . . make complete surgical duplication of consciousness in man an impossibility” (qtd. in Robinson 327). The empirical evidence topples Parfit’s puzzle case.

Robinson imagines Parfit asking these questions about the My Division case: "So how can I survive as only one of the two people? What can make me one of them rather than the other?" Robinson responds:  “One answer is to question the wisdom of taking the imagined case seriously. . . . It is contrary to everything known about human brains to suppose that their two hemispheres are “exactly similar” (324). Wilkes reflects that matters are rarely as straightforward as many philosophers would like them to be: "As [J.] Austin said, oversimplification is something which 'one might be tempted to call the occupational disease of philosophers if it were not their occupation'" (qtd. in Wilkes 38).  

 

Indeterminate Answers

In the My Division case, the answer to this question is indeterminate to a Reductionist: which resultant person, if either, will be me? If I was a particular Cartesian Ego, Parfit suggests, that could explain how one of the resulting persons could be me, if my Ego regained consciousness in that one person (Reasons 258). However, a case could be made that such an operation may be impossible precisely because persons are Cartesian Egos, or because of some further fact, the essence of which precludes such an operation from being successful.

Nevertheless, Parfit thinks he has refuted the Ego view. A Reductionist is content to think that the outcome is that two persons do, in fact, survive, and that each one will be psychologically continuous with the original person. It is irrational, to a Reductionist, to regard the prospect of division in the triplet's case as death, since it was agreed upon (based on Parfit's criteria of Relation R) that one should survive in another twin's division case, where there would be only one surviving person after a half-brain transplant. The hurdle to overcome in the triplet's case, in terms of identity, is duplication, because I cannot be two different people. If someone offered one a drug that was supposed to double one’s life span, and one regarded taking that drug the same as death, then one is being irrational according to this view. Likewise, one should be glad that in My Division, one’s Relation R continues on in two separate persons. It would be somewhat like having doubled one’s life span, only the lives of the two resulting persons are lived concurrently. Parfit proclaims that one should clearly be able to see that survival in terms of Relation R matters more than personal identity. If this can be agreed upon, and therefore the view that identity matters is abandoned, then one can say that neither of the resultant people will be identical to the original and that the original person is about to die (Reasons 264). Besides, in this case, Parfit asks, “How could a double success be a failure?” (“Personal Identity” 167).

Assuming the validity of using this hypothetical case, this view seems plausible. However, I still cannot conceive of myself (my Relation R) going off, literally, in two directions as two different persons. Let us say that one of these resultant persons becomes a successful Philosopher and the other becomes a successful novelist. We may reason thusly, as Parfit admits, that if I am neither of these two people, then they are not fulfilling my ambitions. If that is still a concern, then identity is what matters (Reasons 264). But one should not take this view, according to Parfit. When considering one’s relation to each person surviving the operation, one would ask if there is some vital component missing that would be present in ordinary survival. Parfit thinks there is not. Since nothing is missing, there is nothing about the nature of one’s relation to the two surviving people that would cause one to claim that one failed to survive. The only thing wrong is the duplication (“Psychological View” 256).

Parfit reiterates the question: "Is what matters personal identity, or relation R?" In ordinary cases (which can be taken to mean real life), Parfit admits, we do not have to make such a decision or distinction because these relations coincide. But in a case like My Division where the relations do not coincide we must decide what matters, identity or Relation R (“Psychological View” 257). At this point, however, such a decision is not warranted. Parfit has failed to convince us that his view of the unity of consciousness is sound. As already described, Parfit had stated that if it had not been shown through commissurotomy patients that one’s consciousness could be divided into two separate streams then the view that we really are indivisible Egos could be supported. Since Parfit puts much weight on empirical evidence to support My Division even while admitting that it may be impossible, others have pointed out the problems with this thought experiment.

 

Survival Is More Important Than Identity

Let us examine how Parfit carries through with his project. Because many are sympathetic with Parfit’s ethical theories, it is important to analyze the full scope of his metaphysical arguments underpinning his moral stance. He suggests that one could say that one survived as both new persons in My Division and still imply identity. For example, one could think of the two persons as composing a third person in a manner like the Pope's three crowns are one crown. However, Parfit does not like this solution because it keeps the language of identity at the expense of changing the concept of a person. Instead, he advocates giving up the language of identity, stating that one survives as two different people. This is a more flexible way of thinking about identity that allows us to conceive how one person can survive as two. Furthermore, he reinforces that this view "treats survival as a matter of degree." Whereas identity is an all-or-nothing relation, relations that matter in survival are relations of degree. Parfit asserts: "If we ignore this, we shall be led into quite ill-grounded attitudes and beliefs" (“Personal Identity” 168-9; 172).

Duplication

Parfit creates more thought experiments that produce “branch-line” type of cases. For example, in Teletransportation, a “new and improved” scanner is used, which records information, but one does not get destroyed immediately. A person is replicated on Mars, then the original one (on Earth) dies soon after that (Reasons 199). With each of these types of cases, replications, or duplications, of persons may not be considered identity. Parfit uses these cases to further his claim that these are cases of survival, to one degree or another, and that the survival relation matters more than identity. One should not consider that one’s death on Earth is almost as bad as ordinary death if one has a Replica on Mars who is psychologically related to the original one of Earth. Instead, according to Parfit, one should consider this "about as good as ordinary survival" (“Psychological View” 229). After all, with normal Teletransportation, most people who watch science fiction television and movies consider this kind of process as simply traveling (such as when Captain Kirk in Star Trek pleads: "beam me up, Scottie!"). The main difference in this example with the new scanner is the duplication problem—the same type of identity problem encountered with the My Division case.

Refuting Physical Criterion for

  Personal Identity

 

In order to flesh out the concern about degrees of survival relationships, Parfit uses another tactic while still employing thought experiments. He attempts to demonstrate that questions about identity can be empty questions with no determinate answer. He lays out his aims: "One is to suggest a sense of "survive" which does not imply identity. Another is to show that most of what matters in survival are relations of degree. A third is to show that none of these relations needs to be described in a way that presupposes identity" (“Personal Identity” 171). He introduces the Physical Spectrum case to counter Bernard Williams' view that advocates the physical criterion for personal identity. Williams concludes, according to Parfit, "that if my brain continues to exist, and to be the brain of a living person, I shall be that person. This would be so even if, between myself now and myself later, there would be no psychological connections" (“Psychological View” 243).

In this case, let us say there are 100 possible operations to be performed. In a case at the near end, scientists replace 1% of one’s brain and 1% of one’s body with material made of new organic matter which contains copies of one's own cells. In the middle of this spectrum, 50% of one’s body and brain are replaced. Near the far end, 99%, and at the farthest end, one’s complete body and brain are replaced only after they are first destroyed and a replica is made at a later time. One sees that there is no physical continuity at the farthest end of this spectrum. Parfit suggests that such near end cases for bodily replacements are now possible, given the organ and cell transplants that are quite successful. He realizes that most of the far end cases will remain impossible, but this impossibility is merely technical. He declares, “Since I use these cases to discover what we believe, this impossibility is irrelevant” (Reasons 234).

Before this is categorically swept away as being irrelevant, think about a possible explanation about why all through the spectrum these cases may be impossible. Stairs cites Jaegwon Kim's analysis in pointing out that the common conception that wholes are composed entirely of their parts is probably a mistaken notion. This notion suggests that if you were able to make an atom-for-atom copy of something, then the replicated object will be an exact duplicate of the original at all levels. However, according to Kim, quantum mechanics discloses that this thesis is false "even for a single pair of electrons" (Stairs 467-8).  This has to do with supervenience theory that is beyond the scope of this paper. However, it is important to acknowledge that there are physics theorists who would not subscribe to the kind of Reductionism that Parfit advocates.

Nevertheless, for the sake of continuing on with Parfit's logic in order to understand his conclusions, this impossibility will be considered irrelevant at this time in the discussion. If one continues to believe that one’s identity must be determinate, given these cases, Parfit claims that one must therefore believe that somewhere along the spectrum there is a sharp borderline where one ceases to exist. If one does draw a line arbitrarily, then there cannot be any rational or moral significance to where one can regard the one case, on the one side of the line, as good as ordinary survival and the other case, on the other side of the line, as bad as ordinary death. This arbitrary decision cannot justify any claim about what matters. Reductionism entails that, in some cases, questions about personal identity are indeterminate and that they are empty questions. 

Robinson disagrees with this argument, and suggests that further facts are being overlooked. He thinks that psychological properties supervene upon physiological properties, and that some psychological properties are essential properties of one’s self and some are contingent. According to this view, properties of the brain underlie psychological properties. Therefore, changes in brain cells that underlie essential properties do affect our identity. Robinson avers that explaining survival involves understanding the properties, the facts, over and above those about psychological continuity and connectedness. This, he asserts, “cannot be done independently of a theory about the nature, unity, and continuity of consciousness” (328). 

A Reductionist would have an aversion to assigning such abstruse properties to brain cells, and would stick to his claim about indeterminacy in such spectrum cases. Although Robinson’s view seems plausible, there is much in current literature to support the view that there is not a unity, but, rather, a plurality in consciousness per se. For example, Daniel Dennett provides a good case for plurality throughout his book Consciousness Explained. It is beyond the scope of this paper to examine the nature of consciousness. However, any theory about the nature of persons and personal identity must give some account about the nature of consciousness.

Humean Bundle Connection

Parfit realizes that it is natural for one to believe that one's identity must be determinate. One naturally thinks that in any situation there should be a simple “yes” or “no” answer to the question: am I about to die? (“Psychological View” 243). The Humean Bundle Theory, Parfit presumes, should enable one to reject this belief. You are not a separate entity according to this view, so one can describe exactly what will happen in various cases without having to answer a question about what will happen to you. If you had fifty percent of your cells replaced with exact duplicates, it would be "a mere choice of words" whether to call the resulting person you or whether to call her your Replica. Parfit asks, "How could it be a real question what would happen to you, unless you are a separately existing ego, distinct from a brain and body . . .?" (“Divided Minds” 86). 

Reproduction Survival Experiments

Parfit provides another line of reasoning to help one get over one’s unhealthy attachment to the importance of one’s identity. He discusses survival in terms of human reproduction. While he attempted (somewhat) to stay within the confines of scientific possibilities with various scenarios described above about imaginary surgeries, he goes far afield of reality by proposing ways in which humans do reproduce in order to make his case for survival and identity without further facts. Reviewing a few of these cases will demonstrate the bizarre nature of these kinds of thought experiments.

What would it mean if two people were to fuse into one, such that the resulting person would q-remember the lives of the two former individuals? Those who regard survival as a matter of all-or-nothing would regard this as death for the two beginning persons. Parfit recognizes the challenges presented by such a prospect as this. How would the characteristics and desires of the former individuals get blended? Nevertheless, he maintains that “only the very self-satisfied would think of this as death.” Parfit thinks that fusion is neither definitively survival nor clearly a failure to survive. His point in this experiment is to demonstrate that "what matters in survival can have degrees" (“Personal Identity” 172-3).  Parfit does not discuss this fusion process in terms of gender. It does not make sense for a man and woman to fuse together: what would be the gender of the resultant person? Without providing for any restrictions in this process, then a fundamental part of human nature, i.e., sexuality, is disregarded. Even if this fusion process were a plausible possibility to consider, would anyone feel confident about the outcome of such a fusion? It seems that one would have qualms that the other person in a fusion partnership would have q-intentioned future aspirations in a stronger or contradictory manner than one has done so before the fusion process.

If fusion does not meet one’s fancy, then one should consider the prospect of natural division, whereby one is to imagine beings that would divide into two separate persons, much like an amoeba divides. In this example, the original person, A, divides into B1 and B2. B1, in turn, divides later into C1 and C2. B2 divides into C3 and C4. In the next generation, C1 becomes D1 and D2, C2 becomes D3 and D4, C3 becomes D5 and D6, and so on (Parfit, “Personal Identity” 173). One can envision a tree structure diagram, with one, A, at the root and branching off into several generations of future, seemingly exactly similar, persons. This can be construed as an inversion of a family tree diagram in which one traces one's roots back through several generations whereby one can see a connection to many ancestors within that family tree structure.  

In a normal family tree structure, the diagram shows an individual at the bottom of the tree, A, with one's father, F, and mother, M, at the next generation back level.  Going up the tree structure, next, then, are one's father’s parents: one’s grandfather, G1, and grandmother, G2; and one's mother’s parents, G3, and G4. The next level depicts one's great-grandparents, GG1 through GG8, and so on. Family traditions and values normally get handed down through direct psychological contact with one’s family members and associates of family members. Parfit's new mode is a perversion of the normal type of human reproduction whereby one’s connectedness to one's past generations is through the passing down of genetic properties, family values, and family story-memories.

With the normal model, one can understand the general claim that the more remote the ancestor from the past, the less direct psychological connectedness one will have. With Parfit’s tree of future selves from natural division, the farther into the future, the less direct psychological relations one will have with a distant future self. Q-memories, in time, will be replaced by others. The same holds for other q-relationships such as q­-desires, and so forth. The main point Parfit wants to make with this supposition is that survival and relationships with one's “past selves” and “future selves” should be treated as relations of degrees. With this method of reproduction, one has the most connectedness with the immediate past and future selves (“Personal Identity” 173).

Now, put these two processes together and imagine another type of human whereby one reproduces by fusing every autumn, and then divides every spring. This would make a human a kind of everlasting being in which psychological relations would hold only over limited periods of time. Parfit claims that direct psychological relations would hold only between those parts which are close to each other in time. According to this view, when one gets to the point where one’s character has undergone a significant change, or where one no longer has memories of a certain period, one would say: “It was not I who did that, but an earlier self.” Parfit claims that this is a very natural way of thinking and talking. It is entirely a matter of choice whether, when talking about any of these persons along the fusion-division chain, one would say “I”, “one of my future selves,” or “a descendant self” (“Personal Identity” 175). Again, his whole point in these imagined cases is that survival is a matter of degrees. Parfit goes on to describe yet another type of imaginary being where there is neither division nor fusion, but there are everlasting bodies that gradually change over periods of time.

 

Do Parfit’s Puzzle Cases Convince?

At this point, enough cases of Parfit's imaginary beings have been described for one to understand the picture he is painting. He has made a logical progression from the My Division case, to the Physical Spectrum scenario, and through various forms of alternative human reproduction, in order to argue that survival is more important than identity, and to prove that survival is a matter of degrees and is not always determinate. His view that unity of consciousness only applies to the immediate moment is too narrow, and his rejection of the wider view of unity of consciousness relies too heavily on evidence that consciousness is split in commissurotomy patients. Based on that evidence, he launches into impossible cases in order to tease apart human survival and personal identity. He acknowledges that in ordinary cases we do not have to make a decision between survival and identity. However, he wants us to decide in favor of survival and indeterminacy based in large part on a series of cases that ignore the nature of human reproduction. Because he has relied solely on science fiction thought experiments to logically prove that survival is more important than identity, he has proven his case only in some possible other world. He has not provided a convincing argument that human survival can be separated from personal identity in this world.

He admits that one's belief that identity is what matters is hard to vanquish, especially in light of discussions about problem cases that actually occur: cases like ones involving amnesia or brain damage. Nevertheless, he considers that the My Division case produces a breach in this belief: therefore, the remaining certainty should be easy to topple (“Personal Identity” 170). What, then, would be the moral and ethical implications if society at large accepted Parfit’s views? A final argument against Parfit’s theory will now be presented to demonstrate that the consequences of accepting his view are absurd.


CHAPTER 6

MORAL IMPLCATIONS OF PARFIT’S IDENTITY

THEORIES: A MOVE FROM ETHICAL EGOISM

 TOWARD IMPERSONAL ALTRUISM

Overview

In this section, it is explained why Parfit's personal identity theories are deeply disturbing to some because of the moral implications resulting from such a view. It will be shown why Parfit thinks this view liberates one from morose feelings resulting from thinking about one's eventual demise. Parfit's account, if true, defeats the moral principle of egoism, or ethical self-interest. One will see how adopting Relation R concepts enables one to be more impartial and to move away from ethical egoism and toward rational altruism. Parfit advocates for radically new policies to enable widespread political and social changes. He is a proponent for these policies: a distribution of wealth, paternalistic government intervention to prevent great imprudence by individuals, a legal distinction between persons and humans enabling the killing of humans via abortion and euthanasia, and less punishment the further away from a crime a convict is with respect to his Relation R in regard to the crime. Documentation for these positions will be provided in the details that follow.

If one does not accept Parfit's view of personal identity, then one cannot accept the metaphysical links he attempts to forge when making his case for altruism. Even if one did subscribe to this view, difficulties with the kinds of moral and ethical changes Parfit is advocating are pointed out. This section ends with a brief discussion about moral implications from other personal identity theories in order to demonstrate further the importance of this topic.

Parfit reveals other Philosophers' criticisms about his account. Reid thinks that all ethical rights and obligations are undermined with this view that eliminates any further fact that may ensure determinacy in personal identity. G. Madell claims that the Relation R theory of personal identity "is utterly destructive of a whole range of our normal moral attitudes." V. Haksar claims that Parfit's view undermines all human rights and moral constraints, and is "incompatible with any kind of humane morality" (qtd. in Parfit, “Personal Identity, Rationality” 312-13). Parfit agrees that most people would find it "deeply disturbing" if such a truth about personal identity had this kind of impact.

Some may think that the Reductionist View must be false if these were the implications. However, Parfit judges that this would not be a valid argument to reject this view: "The truth may be disturbing." Just like many people are deeply disturbed about the claim that the Universe was not created by a benevolent God, that feeling alone cannot show the claim to be false (“Personal Identity, Rationality” 313). Mary Midgley, it seems, would agree with Parfit's reasoning along these lines. For example, she thinks that we have backed into "the social atomism which underlies Social Contract thinking" because the consequences of more organic, hierarchical systems were such that people got rid of the conceptual basis for those systems in favor of the more separate atomistic social structure that is prevalent in the western world (469).

Why does Parfit go to such imaginative, albeit creative, lengths to stress the importance of survival in terms of psychological connectedness (Relation R)?  His motivation is to underpin an ethical code with a metaphysical principle and to demonstrate that the prevailing moral principle of self-interest and egoism per se has no force. In the first section of his book Reasons and Persons, Parfit provides a strong argument, independent from this argument about the supremacy of survival over identity, that the theory of self-interest is self-defeating. Although one can agree with his line of reasoning in that regard, he does not provide a self-defeating case against all forms of ethical egoism. For example, Ayn Rand, in most of her fiction and non-fiction, presents arguments for individualism and a form of rational egoism that does not seem to be self-defeating. Her view of ethics entails what she calls the Trader Principle whereby one cannot ask others to sacrifice themselves or their desires for one’s own aims. Conversely, one should never sacrifice one’s self for the sake of others’ goals and desires. Rand also believes that it is important to underpin ethical theories with metaphysical principles, including the nature of persons.[4]

With Parfit’s view, if we can concede that there will be some psychological connectedness to all (of our) future selves, and we can also concede that this is what matters instead of whether we continue on as some kind of further fact entity, then the implications concerning our beliefs in codes of morality are far-reaching.

 

Contemplating One’s Demise

Parfit expresses exhilaration about the liberating effects of his way of thinking about one’s self: “When I believed that my existence was such a further fact, I seemed imprisoned in myself. My life seemed like a glass tunnel, through which I was moving faster every year, and at the end of which there was darkness. When I changed my view, the walls of my glass tunnel disappeared” (Reasons 281).

While most people become depressed, or at least somewhat anxious, when they think of their eventual demise, Parfit suggests that other people become closer to one who adopts his view: one becomes less concerned about one’s own life and more concerned about the lives of others. Although there will no longer be direct chains of connectedness, as there are in normal personal existence, there will continue to be memories about one’s life, perhaps thoughts which will have been influenced by one, and deeds done as a result of one's advice or prior actions. Parfit judges: “This is all there is to the fact that there will be no one living who will be me.” He thinks that this way of thinking about death is “less bad” (Reasons 281).

However, this way of thinking about how one’s life even after death continues to influence others is shared by Non-Reductionists. They just do not subscribe to the metaphysical links that Parfit wishes to install. Parfit thinks that the chains of connectedness should be considered somehow more firm from one generation to the next.  He wants people to feel more metaphysically linked to past and future generations in order to guide them away from selfish, egocentric behavior. He needs his science fiction puzzle cases to make this metaphysical distinction, and to provide for the connection of individual persons into a universal caring family.

Parfit equates Egoism with the fear of death, when one expresses “the regret that so much of one’s only life should have gone by.” He believes that this emotional sentiment is not necessarily instinctive, and he judges it to be bad, brought about because of one's common view of personal identity (“Personal Identity” 176). People should also change their stance when faced with any kind of suffering. Instead of saying, "the person suffering will be me," one should say, "there will be suffering that will be related, in certain ways, to these present experiences." This way of redescribing the facts makes suffering seem less bad to Parfit (“Psychological View” 260). Parfit appears to be advocating an absurd position that one should distance one's self from one's self. 

 

A Reductionist Look at Self-Interest

There are just two main competitors in the field of morality, according to Parfit. One is the Self-Interest theory based on the principle that the supremely rational aim for each person is that his own life, on the whole, go as well as possible. Even though both Reductionists and Non-Reductionists alike agree that each person is different, each with individual lives to lead, Parfit agrees with Henry Sidgwick in claiming that it is the deeper truth view of Non-Reductionists that becomes the foundation underlying all reasons for acting. This view, then, is the basis for the Self-Interest theory about rationality. Sidgwick thinks another equally rational ultimate aim for humans is that things go, on the whole, as well as possible for everyone (Parfit, Reasons 329). Many believe that this second objective should be the foundation of our moral theory. Some agree with Sidgwick that when morality conflicts with self-interest, one cannot answer the question: what is the most rational thing to do?  Sidgwick suggests, according to Parfit, that one could refute the Self-Interest theory if one took a different position on personal identity. This is precisely what Parfit advocates (Reasons 329). These remarks demonstrate Parfit's reasoning:

On this [Non-Reductionist] view, it is a deep truth that all of a person's life is as much his life. If we are impressed by this truth—about the unity of each life—the boundaries between lives will seem to be deeper. This supports the claim that, in the moral calculus, these boundaries cannot be crossed. On the Reductionist View, we are less impressed by this truth. We regard the unity of each life as, in its nature, less deep, and as a matter of degree. We may therefore think the boundaries between lives . . . . They may then seem less morally important. (“Personal Identity, Rationality” 319-20)

Even though he is making a strong argument that the Reductionist View and its moral consequences are good, Parfit needs to explain why he is still "much more concerned" about his own future than he is about a mere stranger's future. The reason, he concludes, is based on natural evolutionary forces. He claims, "Special concern for one's own future would be selected by evolution." This ethically neutral fact does not support nor undermine any claim about whether this attitude of self-concern is justified. He admits that it is still an open question about whether it is justified (“Personal Identity, Rationality” 302-3). One could argue, however, that an evolutionary explanation goes toward emphasizing a certain aspect about the nature of human beings and therefore should be included in an account of personal identity. On the other hand, one could counter this argument by saying that this biological evolutionary need for self-concern is no longer necessary since we have come so far in our non-biological evolutionary processes of building civilizations.

 

Impartial Altruism

A companion to the Self-Interest theory is one of Common-Sense Morality. According to this notion, one should give to one’s children, and to others that one values most, some kinds of priority. Parfit’s Relation R helps to move one toward rational altruism, enabling one to be more impersonal and impartial. According to Relation R, there are cases where one should not give priorities to one's own children, but rather, should do what would be best for everyone’s children, considered impartially. If one follows this principle for other relationships such as with parents, friends, neighbors, and so forth, then impersonality proves to provide the ‘better’ outcome for everybody (Reasons 444).

 

Social Changes

Distribution of Wealth

This altruistic view naturally leads to specific social and political consequences. For one result, Parfit argues in favor of a distribution of wealth. He contends, "Though every gain in welfare matters, it also matters who gains. Certain distributions are, we claim, morally preferable. We ought to give some priority to helping those who are worse off, through no fault of theirs. And we should try to aim for equality" (“Personal Identity, Rationality” 320).

 

Paternalism

Since society should abandon the classical self-interest theory, according to Parfit, he pushes his views further for an expansion of moral theory to include an appeal to Consequentialism. This provides for a paternalistic protection of persons from their own great imprudence. Whereas currently very few would claim that imprudence per se is morally wrong, this would change under Parfit's scheme. For example, if a young person takes up smoking, she may be imposing on herself a premature death. Parfit proposes, "We should claim that it is wrong to impose on anyone, including such a future self, the risk of such a death. More generally, we should claim that great imprudence is morally wrong. This claim strengthens the case for paternalistic intervention. We ought not to do to our future selves what it would be wrong to do to other people." He claims the right to keep people from acting wrongly towards themselves. He supposes that this claim would not hold sway over minor wrongdoing, but that it would be our duty to prevent serious wrongdoing, "even if this involves coercion" (“Personal Identity, Rationality” 310-11).

One can argue that paternalism per se can be appropriately incorporated within our society’s moral structure. For example, most would agree that laws enforcing the wearing of car seat belts and motorcycle helmets are good laws, in spite of any personal freedoms they may inhibit. However, it seems that adopting Parfit’s views would entail an inordinate amount of legislation and morality policies in order to limit personal freedoms such that persons would not affect serious wrongdoing against themselves. Although this is not a philosophical argument against his position, one can only imagine the consequential legal quagmire that would ensue.

Korsgaard argues that one can live one's own life only if one is free from this kind of interference. Freedom is necessary for one to be one's own person. Her unity of agency view does not preclude a concern for the future of larger agencies with which one is associated. One usually has a present and future personal concern for one's family, workplace, certain projects, and state or country. This personal concern that begins with one's self, and then widened as just described, can develop further into ever-widening spheres that does not necessarily preclude a concern for the Earth's environment and fellow creatures at large (334-5).  

On the extreme opposite end of Korsgaard's view, Frithjof Bergmann puts freedom at the low end of his hierarchy of values. Because freedom can bring one nothing that could be considered one's "brutal, bare necessities," and because in many cultures most have lived in hostile circumstances without freedom, then one should consider freedom a luxury. Bergmann thinks that we are spoiled to want more than these others have, and that it is presumptuous to demand freedom. He presumes that freedom is necessary to provide "the consonance between my life and my nature or my identifications," but this should only be a consideration after brute and bare necessities are obtained. According to his assessment, one should feel guilty for wanting freedom when there are so many without. For example, he claims "that the free pursuit of one's material gain deserves perhaps only a very lowly status. . . . To take advantage of every manner of interdependency while one acquires, but then to shout ‘freedom’ at the sign of the first claim by others should by now provoke a laugh, or maybe anger—but not a philosophical debate" (419-20). Nevertheless, one cannot simply dismiss property rights theories by claiming that any such ideas are not philosophical in nature. However, that would be a subject for another thesis.

Abortion

Returning to Parfit, on the issue of abortion the Non-Reductionist would claim that there must be a moment when one starts to exist, because one’s existence is an all-or-nothing proposition. A Reductionist, using a spectrum perspective, would not believe that at every moment from conception to birth one either does or does not exist.  One can now believe that the transition from a fertilized ovum to a person takes time and is a matter of degree. Some, like Locke, make a distinction between human beings and persons, and those who hold this distinction may claim that a human being becomes a person only at the time one becomes self-conscious. With this view, there is room for disagreement about whether a fetus is a person, even granting that it becomes a human being before the end of pregnancy. One may, under this reasoning, consider that only the killing of persons is wrong (Reasons 321-2). Of course, Parfit still faces the dilemma of deciding at what point along the continuum during pregnancy a person emerges, and therefore, it would be morally wrong to abort after that point in time.

Euthanasia

At the other end of one’s life, using such a distinction, euthanasia can now be considered in terms of human beings versus persons. If  someone is in a coma, without ever a chance to regain consciousness (assuming that one could ever know this for certain), does one still consider this a person or not? Parfit declares that one should believe that person has ceased to exist, and it would therefore be alright to end that human life (Reasons 323). Should one claim, like Parfit’s example suggests, that killing human beings that cannot be considered persons is morally acceptable? This is the logical conclusion one might draw if one subscribes to Parfit's account of personal identity.

Punishment

What does Parfit have to say about just deserts? Locke thought one should not be punished for a crime that one could not remember. Many people think that this view is morally repugnant. Parfit admits that he has not yet found a good resolution to the argument claiming that psychological continuity is what matters regarding punishment for past crimes. But he is willing to commit himself to the general claim that the further away in time in which a convict is connected to a crime, the less punishment he deserves. Parfit illustrates what he means. Suppose a ninety year old man who now holds a Nobel Peace Prize confessed that he had beaten a policeman in a drunken brawl when he was twenty years old. Since he was psychologically far removed from this crime, however serious the crime, he may not now deserve to be punished. Parfit suggests that this is the reason why many countries have Statutes of Limitations (Reasons 326).

In many cases, however, these statutes are written for practical, rather than moral, reasons. This may be inferred by the fact that in many legal systems there is no such limitation for the crime of murder. Parfit’s reasoning, however, taken to its logical conclusion, seems to suggest that a criminal who can hide well from justice—one who distances himself from his crime with enough time—does not deserve punishment, while one who is caught early after the crime, does deserve punishment. Lloyd Fields points out yet another major problem with Parfit’s claim.  Because many experiences can lie dormant in one’s memories, using Parfit’s criterion, jurors would always be in a state of doubt about whether a person deserves more punishment than he appears to deserve. A criminal may be in actuality more psychologically connected to the crime than he appears, but his blocked, dormant q-memories prevent a full disclosure of his true connectedness (437). In the current legal system, a juror needs to be convinced about a defendant’s guilt based on evidence presented regardless of what the defendant says or remembers. Under Parfit’s view, as previously mentioned, the further away one is psychologically removed from a crime, the less punishment one deserves. Once again, one can only imagine the consequential legal quagmire that would ensue if this view were to be embraced.

Environment

Regarding environmentalism, Parfit uses an example whereby someone shoots an arrow into a distant wood, and, sight unseen, it wounds someone else. If he knew that someone else was there, he would be guilty of gross negligence. Even if he did not know someone else was there, and even if the woods were far away, he is still not excused from negligence. Parfit maintains that one should have the same views about the effects on people who are temporally remote (Reasons 357). Rational egoists would agree with future-generation altruists in that one should not use, or misuse, natural resources because of sheer whim or desire, with no rational purpose.

 

Unity

For the Non-Reductionist, the unity in one's life is a given (further) fact. Parfit’s Reductionism is, on the whole, far more impersonal, giving less importance to the unity of individual lives and to boundaries between lives, and giving more importance to experiences per se. He states, "It becomes more plausible to claim that, just as we are right to ignore whether people come from the same or different nations, we are right to ignore whether experiences comes within the same or different lives" (“Personal Identity, Rationality” 321). Korsgaard points out the circularity in Parfit's theory: "If you begin with the view that a person is a subject of experiences, and take away the subject, you are indeed left with nothing but experiences. But you will begin with that view only if you assume from the start that having experiences is what life is all about" (338).

On the other hand, for Parfit, “unity” seems to be a worthy goal for one to achieve:

On the Reductionist View, the unity of our lives is a matter of degree, and is something that we can affect. . . . And we can give our lives greater unity in ways that express or fulfill our particular values and beliefs. Since the Reductionist View gives more importance to how we choose to live, and to what distinguishes different people, this is a way in which it is more personal. (Reasons 446)

Instead of the concept of unity, the word meaning or continuity would fit better in this context. Nevertheless, we can understand this line of thinking when we consider expressions people commonly use, such as “I’ve got to get my act together.” Parfit is describing a kind of building block, designer approach to creating a life. But, since he thinks of persons as being like nations, this approach can produce unity only if the values and beliefs are consistent.

Values and beliefs can, and often do, change over time within individuals. This would be no threat to a Non-Reductionist unity. Parfit is presupposing that Non-Reductionists do not place importance on values and beliefs, because unity is guaranteed. Although unity is a fundamental axiom with Non-Reductionists, it does not follow that it is not important how one chooses to live, guided by values and beliefs. In a footnote added in response to criticism, Parfit expresses regret: "I should not have claimed that connectedness was more important than continuity." Nevertheless, in that same footnote he reiterates the kernel of his theory on personal identity (“Personal Identity” 178).

 

Contrast With Other Personal

Identity Theories

One can further acknowledge the importance of this topic by reviewing some ethical consequences from other theories about personal identity. This will be a brief summary of a few of those perspectives. For example, using his consciousness (memory) criteria, Locke cites human laws whereby a sane man is not punished for what he did when he was insane: the law, therefore, treats him as two separate persons. This is substantiated by our common way of speaking, Locke contends, when we say things like "one is not himself, or is beside himself" (120). Kolak and Martin point out that a strict interpretation of this view has a similar consequence as what Parfit advocates: it would mean that "Smith actually murdered Jones only if he remembers having done it" (“Personal Identity Introduction” 164).

With this next example one can see how Jaak Panksepp draws a moral conclusion based on a minimal theory about the self. He theorizes that the emotional power of music may be the result of sound waves resonating with some kind of neural infrastructure of the self. This, in turn, produces bodily effects such as chills. One would be able to make empirical predictions based on this kind of possibility. He then makes this moral leap: "The recognition  that such processes may be central components of human development (Panksepp, 1999a) may also encourage us to consider undertaking positive forms of social engineering . . ." (126).

Martin proposes a self-improvement engineering project whereby there would be some type of procedure by which one could choose all the ways one wanted to change physically and psychologically. I call this the "sell-your-soul" view. Martin posits that most people would opt for this kind of radical change via some type of operation even if it meant that one would lose one's identity, because one would lose all of one's memories to obtain those benefits. He presents a convincing argument with the stunning conclusion that many people wish to be fulfilled more than they want to be who they currently are. Clearly, loss of identity under this scenario does not seem to be as bad as death (294-5). However, one wonders what kind of a human society there would be if everyone, or nearly everyone, opted for such a procedure. It seems that maintaining any kind of personal relationship would be meaningless, if not impossible, whereby someone in the relationship could so abruptly and radically change. However, this qualm about such a possibility does not present a philosophical argument against Martin's supposition. Nevertheless, note that this is another instance of using imaginary thought experiments to explore the nature of persons.

For a final example, Pickering questions the implications of his theory: "What then might be at stake, ethically speaking, when deciding whether to consider the self as a thing or as a process? My judgement is that it is an engagement with environmental issues." A process view of the nature of persons and personal identity involves an extension of self-interest, according to Pickering, whereby the needs of other people and other entities "emerge as covalent with one's own." He judges that one's philosophical viewpoint can easily cloud one's conclusions about the nature of personal identity. He suggests that one may come to a view about personal identity based upon the ethical implications of such a view: "What we assume to be the value, that is the ethical entailments of one or the other view, are also likely subtly to condition what we experience 'the self' to be" (74-5).

Although there are additional moral and ethical implications based upon other personal identity views, enough examples have been provided to demonstrate the profound impact that personal identity views have on moral and ethical theory. One has grasped that Parfit's Reductionist view of personal identity has far reaching implications and that other thinkers’ views entail sweeping changes to the moral order of society. Parfit advocates for a move away from Self-Interest and toward an impersonal altruistic code of ethics. Locke's memory criterion for personal identity presents challenges for a justice system. Panksepp wants us to consider the need for social engineering based upon a theory about a possible neural infrastructure of the self. Lastly, Martin questions one’s attachment to one’s own identity when it seems that one would gladly trade one’s identity for a chance to become fulfilled.


CHAPTER 7

QUESTIONING THE USE OF SCIENCE FICTION

THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS

The prevailing non-reductionist "common sense" view of personal identity, i.e., that we are each enduring individuals, is the basis for our current legal systems and for the Self -Interest view of morality. If philosophers come to have a different view of personal identity, or if they think survival can be separated from identity and that survivial is more important, then it follows naturally that they would call for the moral and legal systems to also be swept aside. Because of this consequence, I next examine whether some philosophers’ methodological approach is appropriate for the concepts they are investigating. A case is made against relying heavily on the science fiction type of thought experiments for drawing conclusions about the questions of personal identity, and their resulting implications.

 

Why Thought Experiments Are Used

Arguments against some conclusions drawn within some specific thought experiments have already been presented. This section examines why thought experiments are used, and how they are used to explore the questions of personal identity. After reviewing these defenses for and objections against using this method, one should be convinced that thought experiments are of a very limited value in determining the nature of persons and personal identity. This method should be considered as only one tool in a toolbox full of other analytical methods from which to derive important conclusions and resulting implications about our subject questions. One could argue for tossing this tool out of the philosophical toolbox altogether when analyzing certain concepts, especially concepts surrounding the questions of personal identity.

Kolak and Martin explain that this method is used in an attempt to determine whether the continuity of physical structures or of psychological structures, or some combination of both, constitutes necessary criteria for personal identity. With such cases, one can posit that either the physical structures are preserved while the psychological ones are disrupted, or vice versa, and then determine whether or not personal identity is preserved or not as a result of the experiment. Thought experiments are often used to separate and put pressure on these elements, because in life they "are always conjoined" (“Personal Identity Introduction” 169). Immediately, a red flag is raised. If these basic elements are always conjoined in real life for human persons, and we are investigating the metaphysical nature of the identity of this concept, they why is it legitimate to separate these elements? A possible answer to this objection may be that if both kinds of structures are necessary for personal identity, then we could more easily come to this conclusion by trying to separate them. It is also legitimate to separate them using thought experiments in order to test the necessity or sufficiency of each criterion.

Parfit thinks that our current false beliefs about what persons are can be best brought to light through the use of imaginary cases. He acknowledges that Ludwig Wittgenstein believes that we can learn little from such stories, and that Willard Quine questions whether the limits of this method are properly heeded. Quine suggests that extreme thought experiments "suggest that words have some logical force beyond what our past needs have invested with them" (qtd. in Parfit, “Psychological View” 228). Nevertheless, Parfit thinks this criticism would be warranted only if we had no reactions to the stories. He proclaims justification for their use because "these cases arouse in most of us strong beliefs," and that it is through their use that we discover the nature of personal identity (“Psychological View” 228). It seems odd that in an era of analytical philosophy in the western world, a philosopher would advocate a method based upon the emotional effects produced. One can argue that religious sermons and stories also produce among listeners strong reactions and beliefs about our human nature—beliefs that usually subscribe to some form of the transcendental, or ego, view of personal identity.

Martin defends the use of such experiments, especially in trying to determine the importance of identity. If one can separate identity per se from other characteristics that normally coexist with it in real life, then one has the opportunity to choose whether identity or some other factor is more important, i.e., survival or some aspect of survival. Without these kinds of stories, Martin claims, it would be difficult to evoke these preferences (292-3). 

 

How Thought Experiments Are Used

Gendler describes the general strategy involved with personal identity thought experiments. In many such cases put forward we can make sense of the scenario. For example, in principle it may be possible that A's brain could be transplanted into B's body. Since we can make sense out of a case, we should then be able to make factual or value judgments about the personal identity criteria involved. Then, based on those results, we could return to actual cases with what we have learned from the imaginary examples. There are two general types of objections to this method, as Gendler points out. The first type, substantive disputes, involves questioning the validity of fundamental aspects of particular cases. For example, one may question whether brain transplants could ever be possible. The second general objection is to question whether our concepts should, or even could, "support all of the implications of our beliefs concerning what is practically, physically, or conceptually possible" (448-9).

Thomas Nagel gives us a good example of a substantive dispute in discussing a version of the My Division case. "It is therefore hard to internalize a conception of myself as identical with my brain: if I am told that my brain is about to be split, and that the left half will be miserable and the right half euphoric, there is no form that my subjective expectations can take, because my idea of myself doesn't allow for divisibility—nor do the emotions of expectation, fear, and hope" (185-86). Another example comes from Andrew Brook in trying to comprehend the Fission case. "I have no difficulty with imagining myself lying down . . . moving into the fissioning machine . . . and then what? I cannot go any further. I cannot imagine myself, i.e., me as I am aware of myself from the inside, becoming two selves . . ." (44).

In spite of these kinds of objections, Gendler maintains that there is nothing "categorically wrong" with such thought experiments even if they concern technical, biological, or physically impossible scenarios. He points out that these kinds of experiments play legitimate roles "in legal reasoning, linguistic theorizing, scientific inquiry and ordinary conversation." What Gendler objects to, however, is when a case is ill-conceived in light of the particular structure of the concept that the experiment is intended to clarify. When one structures the concept of personal identity around a set of necessary and sufficient conditions, and those conditions are used to determine what candidates are selected as comprising that concept, then imaginary cases may assist in separating essential from accidental criteria (449). Parfit seems to agree with Gendler. He admits that most of his cases are either merely technically impossible or that they contravene the laws of nature and are therefore deeply impossible. He claims that this does not matter if the question or what one is trying to show is structured properly. "But," Parfit cautions, "we should bear in mind that, depending on our question, impossibility may make some thought-experiment irrelevant" (“Psychological View” 235).

There are exceptional cases in the real world that enable philosophers to speculate about personal identity where a single body seems to be able to contain more than one aggregation of psychological attributes. These would be cases, for example, of people with Multiple Personality Disorder and of those with other kinds of dissociation. However, as Gendler points out, there are no actual cases where a single set of psychological attributes exist in more than one body (450-1).

Gendler recounts that Locke was the first philosopher to use imaginary cases for our subject questions. He refers back to Locke's emperor and cobbler case, in which the personalities of the emperor and cobbler switched bodies. That was the model for subsequent personal identity thought experiments. This story depends on three things: "(1) that we can make sense of a story in which two personalities 'switch bodies', (2) that we can describe a mechanism by which such a switch might take place, and (3) that that mechanism involves some transfer of substance."  However, Gendler questions whether one should make judgments based on stories where it is described how the world might come to be other than how it currently is configured. Furthermore, Gendler presents an argument that as the stories have become more and more complex, even though we are still able to make sense out of them, the increasing complexity "wreaks havoc with our ability to make reliable judgments."  We come to "see that the initial illusion of certainty about the simple case was only that: an illusion" (454).

 

Einstein’s Example

Some problems with Parfit's My Division case have been noted above. He avers that we can make a reliable judgment from this experiment even though it will probably remain impossible. He declares that this is not grounds for dismissing this case: "There seems to be no similar connection between a particular view about what we really are and the impossibility of dividing and successfully transplanting the two halves of the lower brain." Parfit intends to bolster his claim that it is productive to consider impossible thought experiments by citing the fact that Einstein used thought experiments (“Psychological View” 252). However, Einstein's thought experiments were productive because they pointed the way in which scientists could later devise instruments and mechanisms to test his theories.

For example, Peter Galison reports that Einstein theorized that there was only one kind of magnetism and that it was caused by electrons racing around atomic nuclei in an aligned orientation to behave like tiny magnets. Einstein wondered how one could test this idea. "Suppose that you are standing on a lazy Susan with a gyroscope in each hand, each with its axis pointing away from you and spinning clockwise from your point of view." Thus is the beginning of this thought experiment scenario. He then imagined the whole scenario taking place inside an iron bar. At a later time, Einstein, with a collaborator, built a delicate device to virtually carry out such a scenario, and they were successful in obtaining results to prove his theory. However, it was discovered later that the result from this testing was off by a factor of two in the measurement of magnetism per unit of angular momentum. So, although his commitment to a particular model gave him the impetus about how to conduct the experiment, the results were easy to accept "when blackboard calculation and laboratory results agreed." Galison reminds us of one of Einstein's famous quotes: "No one but a theorist believes his theory; everyone puts faith in a laboratory result but the experimenter himself" (68-9).

Even though this particular concrete experiment did not produce the final answer for the topic at hand, the thought experiment went a long way to guide scientists along correct paths of inquiry. There are other thought experiments inherited from Einstein that proved fruitful in this regard. Wilkes explains that in order for thought experiments to be of any value, whether being used in analyzing scientific or philosophical theories, then it must be clear what aspects of reality remain constant in the imaginary scenario, and what aspects are altered in thought (2). The armchair philosopher must be bound by as stringent constraints as is the laboratory researcher. The philosopher must provide any relevant background conditions against which a thought experiment is set in order to show what difference some particular factor may make: these background conditions must remain constant (6-7).

 

More Problems With Personal Identity

Thought Experiments

Thought experiments that Parfit and others like him put forth to test personal identity concepts have not been so productive. They do not lead us to devise ways to test the theories they are purporting to prove. They only leave us with our imagination, and in many cases the imagination is stretched too far. Therefore, the experiments shed little or no light on the concepts that are being presented. Wilkes judges that most philosophical thought experiments fail "because of the ambiguous uncertainty concerning the relevant background conditions, leaving it unclear whether we have indeed 'established a phenomenon'."  In these kinds of cases we must use further imagination to imagine the possible world in which an experiment is placed (8).

For example, in a fission type of case where one may split like an amoeba, in order to draw any kind of conclusion, we need to know background information such as: Is this an optional procedure? Is it predictable? Does the society in which such reproduction takes place have institutions like marriage? How would that work? Wilkes demonstrates that "the entire background here is incomprehensible. When we ask what we would say if this happened, who, now, are 'we'?" (11). She points out another problem that seems to be at the heart of why personal identity thought experiments are so lacking in solid background information. It is because most of these philosophers know very little, or care little, about biology and physiology (19).

The My Division case provides for a good example of a substantive dispute. Parfit posits that before the operation, one could quasi-intend that one of the resulting persons travels the world and that the other one remains at home. Unless they changed their inherited minds, these new persons would carry out one's intentions (“Psychological View” 255). One wonders how one could go about quasi-intending, or any other quasi-relating, to specific halves of one's brain, to ensure that each resultant person only receives one of the opposing intentions or other psychological relationships that one is trying to convey. One is unable to imagine this “from the inside.”

Another substantive dispute about this case has to do with the logic of assuming that all aspects of Relation R that contribute to character and other aspects of one's psychology, things that one does not need to, or want to, differentiate between the two resultant persons, would be distributed in duplicate and identically between the two halves of the brain. Otherwise, there would be differences between these two halves, possibly important differences that would not carry Relation R to each of the resultant persons. Just because one can supposedly survive with one half of the brain destroyed, or non-functioning, does not mean that one can split a whole functioning brain in half and end up with two qualitatively identical resultant persons. It could be the case that if one loses the function of one half of one's brain, then one becomes psychologically different because of that defect.

Shoemaker makes an observation about the judgments made from branch line cases (that result in two or more supposedly identical persons). These cases purport to demonstrate that the psychological continuity or connectedness involved in survival is more important than identity that normally constitutes that continuity when there is no branching. He tells us that this is the opposite from pre-analytic intuition: "One's initial inclination is to say that if one cares especially about the future person who will be psychologically continuous with one, this is because one believes that that person will be oneself. What reflection on the fission case suggests is that it is just the other way around . . ." (272).

Within the growing complexity of these cases, Gendler mentions those kinds of cases where Locke's third principle for conducting personal identity thought experiments is traversed: where it is imagined that the transfer of information takes place instead of transferring some substance. Examples are the Teletransportation cases and ones where independent replications, or one or more exact duplicates, of human beings are created. These transfers take place as a result of "some causally independent process" (455-6).

 

Unger’s Experiments

Unger, who ascribes to the physical criterion view of personal identity, challenges the notion that the physical approach has been refuted because one would survive a process whereby one ceases to exist moments before one's replica is created out of entirely new matter. He argues along similar lines as does Wilkes. Unger asserts:

In the first place, unless there is reason to think that the case has some basis in reality, it cannot begin to pose a threat to the physical approach. For this approach, it will be remembered, is offered as adequate only relative to the general truth of our world view. And perhaps this case is not, in any relevant way, a realistically possible example. If not, then citing it may provide no real challenge. (203)

Nevertheless, Unger takes up the challenge. He posits that one may retain physical continuity in a case like this if one thinks beyond the ordinary physical view of space and time. With Unger's wide physical continuity view, there could be other physical dimensions that would provide for a "more exotic continuity" for matter. So, this transfer example could be specified such that the original matter will exist throughout the episode because it "may go on a trip into some further physical dimensions." In this manner, the person will exist throughout, because, according to Unger, a person is constituted of matter. With other scenario specifications, for example, "an absolute physical miracle," where ex nihilo new matter replaces old matter that ceased to exist a few moments ago, then one would not survive the episode (203).

It is interesting to note that between Unger's reformulations, he favors the more exotic physics version. However, a much more common world view, albeit a religious one, includes a "Rapture" concept whereby one's bodily matter here on Earth instantly ceases to exist and then is instantly recreated in Heaven. Even though one can make more sense out of the second specification, Unger's view of the physical criteria for personal identity is clear in his preference for an explanation due to some possible laws of physics.

On the other hand, one could argue that one can make more sense out of the exotic physics example Unger has proposed. Stairs provides us with the "many worlds interpretation" of physics that claims that the universe has literally branched. He claims that if this is true, then one's consciousness has split and therefore quantum mechanics has enormous implications regarding our concepts of personal identity. The objections that have been raised regarding fission thought experiments on the grounds that we cannot imagine experiencing such fissioning of our selves is just misguided. According to Stairs, within such a scheme, our experience of the world would be just as it actually is now. "The reason we are not aware of a fissioning of our consciousness is that the branches don't coexist in one space-time. Under normal circumstances, the branches don't interfere with one another" (460-61).

Unger goes on to present a more bizarre case that seems quite far removed from any general truth of our world view that we could believe. He questions the importance of one's very capacity for life while making a judgment about survival. He posits a bionic, integrated, inorganic, and complex structure as a replacement for someone's brain. This new brain will (somehow) carry on this person's psychology. This so-called brain could then be removed from the body and kept functioning in some way. The person will be killed, and then the brain is given a bionic body. Unger asserts that the original person clearly survives this whole process, and that if one were fatally ill, one should have no qualms about undergoing such a procedure: it is determinately true that one would continue to exist (209-10).

Unger thinks that this case supports a physical view of our survival where there only needs to be physically continuous realization of one's mental facilities. There is not a necessary criterion for "any (logically independent) capacity to be alive" (211). It is clear that Unger has not heeded his own advice. He should not have offered this case because it is not adequate to any general truth about one's world view: there is no challenge here. Also, in a case like this, a whole “person” cannot equal the sum of his [its] parts, especially when biological parts are substituted with non-biological parts—parts that hypothetically function the same.

 

Korsgaard On Outside Influence and Pain

 

Korsgaard objects to imaginary cases that involve intervention from outside. For example, Williams suggests a case where A and B will have a body exchange procedure. Before the operation, each person was told that one resulting person will be given a large sum of money, but the other person will be tortured, and they are each asked to make a choice about which treatment should be given to which resultant person. Williams assumes that each person before going into the procedure will want the other-body-person to get the reward. This shows that one does not necessarily care about what happens to one's current body when caring about what happens in the future. He thinks that he has refuted the notion that bodily continuity is a necessary condition for personal identity, and that this mirrors, in some sense, Descartes' phrase, I and my body are "really distinct" (Williams 182-3).

One could stipulate that Williams’ assumption is correct about a person’s choice before going forward with such a body-switch procedure. However, Korsgaard's objection to these kinds of mad surgeon stories is that a person is being changed by intervention, from outside (332). Philosophers would serve their purposes better in order to evoke the kinds of reactions they are seeking if one could imagine changes being initiated by the persons themselves, and as a result of their choices.

It is also significant to Korsgaard that these cases often focus on future pain. "The impersonal character of pain is part of what makes it seem so intrusive." She suggests that Williams' pain examples demonstrate not just that one strongly identifies with one's body, but that one identifies with the animal side of one's human nature. "One might say, a little extravagantly, that the growing human animal is disciplined, frustrated, beaten, and shaped until it becomes a person—and then the person is faced with the task of reintegrating the animal and its needs back into the human life." Korsgaard considers that humans are not very good at this reintegration based on the evidence from psychoanalytic theory, and from the long human history of ambivalence with regard to the animal nature of the species. She muses, "Pain examples serve to show us how vulnerable our animal identity can make our human identity" (332).

 

Drawing Conclusions From Experiments

Gendler recounts a series of related cases that Williams put forth. These are cases that have different combinations of amnesia and transfers of information from the brain of one person to another. Williams concludes that, in this series of cases, the body is the correct criterion of personal identity. Those who advocate that a psychological criterion connotes personal identity come to the opposite conclusion when interpreting the results of this same series of imaginary cases. They claim that in the very first case, "what matters for prudential concern has been lost," and, the Lockean person is thus eliminated. Others think that they can make sense out of the series whereby one could claim that both the physical and psychological criteria are important for personal identity. This reinforces Gendler's claim "that our ability to make sense of imaginary scenarios in which features that coincide in nearly all actual cases are recombined in novel ways far outruns our ability to make judgments about them" (458-9).

Jonathan Shear expresses a similar concern. He states that imaginary cases "can be multiplied without end." However, no matter which position one wants to argue, e.g., to argue for the priority of physical criteria, or for the priority of psychological criteria, "there will be examples that show its inadequacy." By looking through the lens of these thought experiments, one can agree with Shear that we then begin to adopt Hume's skeptical despair over coming to any adequate account of the self and personal identity (410).

 

Real Life Puzzle Cases

Thought-experiments and imaginary cases can be instrumental in discussing the philosophical issue of personal identity. For example, it used to be considered controversial for surgeons to perform heart transplants, or to use artificial hearts in cases where a patient would die otherwise. This was probably disturbing for those who hold to the Physical Criterion of identity, or for those who thought that the further fact about one's identity was seated in the heart. Now, the medical world is struggling over the moral issues of using baboon hearts for this purpose. What about genetic engineering of “test tube” babies? What if brain cells could be synthetically produced? What if human cloning is realized? One could go on, perhaps ad infinitum, with imagination in this arena, and imagination has a purpose here. But notice that, in these examples, one can set up thought experiments within the background of this world where all relevant background constants can be adequately described.

There is a heated debate in America over the issues involved in abortion and the use of embryonic stem cells for research. Because human beings come into existence at the time of conception, it is argued that since it is prima facie immoral to kill human beings, it is therefore immoral to kill embryos. An interesting objection to this argument, as David Shoemaker describes, comes from identity philosophy in examining the real live version of fission, namely, twinning. If a human being comes into existence at the moment of conception, one asks: what happened to the original embryo-human? Does it survive as one of, or both, twins, or not at all, or is the original human a shared stage of the resulting twins? If it dies, then death has somehow occurred with no earthly remains. However, this is what occurs when amoebas split (D. Shoemaker).

At the other end of one’s life, identity issues come into play with advanced directives. Shoemaker poses the puzzle case of a woman who, when in early stages of Alzheimer’s disease, creates a directive stating that no life-saving measures are to be used should she come into a stage of the disease when she would no longer be competent to make informed decisions about her health. After she becomes demented, she develops pneumonia and she would die without life-saving measures. She is quite content in her state of mind at this time. When asked, she states that she wants to live. Should her directive take precedence, or her current wishes? Those with differing identity views will answer this question differently (D. Shoemaker).

In addition, there are many other rich actual “puzzle” cases from which to draw upon for this subject, such as those with these conditions: having amnesia, having Alzheimer’s disease, being comatose, being identical twins, being Siamese twins, having multiple personalities, sex change operation patients, being severely deformed, being severely mentally retarded, and so forth. There is one particular type of an actual case, albeit extremely rare, that clearly stretches the limits of any view of personal identity. In February, 2005, doctors removed one of the heads from a ten-month-old baby born with two heads: a rare condition called craniopagus parasiticus. This condition occurs with conjoined twins when one of the twins fails to develop fully in the womb, but its head and brain does develop. The other fully developed twin is compromised because its heart must serve to pump blood for both heads and brains. There have been only eight known cases like this. This has been the only successful operation of its kind. Before removal and subsequent death of the parasitic head, its eyes blinked and it looked like it could respond and smile.[5] Father Robert Auman, a Catholic Priest, responded to a question posed in an internet forum regarding this case: "In my view, if the second head showed signs of understanding, I would consider it a person. If considered a person, it would not be lawful to deliberately kill it. Even if it would eventually cause the death of the other person, it cannot be considered an unjust aggressor" (Auman). This case stretches the norm of only one brain for one body.

Wilkes considers that "a plethora of here and now actual puzzle-cases" serve the same function that science fiction thought experiments are supposed to effect. But they do so in a more fruitful manner because all of the relevant background information and facts are given. These kind of real life cases "are ready to hand—waiting only to be dug out of the psychological, neurophysiological, medical, psychoanalytic, and anthropological literature." Perhaps one could view these real cases as more interesting than the kind of thought experiments we have been considering, because, as Wilkes muses, the everyday proverb that truth is stranger than fiction seems correct in this venue. So, in order to stretch the limits of the concept of a person, she discusses such cases as fetuses, insanity, fugues, hypnosis, multiple personality, and others (48-49 ff.).


CHAPTER 8

CONCLUSION

Parfit and other Reductionists give these actual cases little or no mention. Although Parfit's imaginary cases are thought provoking, his method is flawed because of his reliance on impossible cases, especially in regard to reproduction, in order to define the nature of humans. While he demands empirical evidence to support a Cartesian Ego, or Further Fact Non-Reductionist view, he expects one to accept his logical conclusions based on science fiction. The far-reaching implications of Parfit’s views on personal identity and survival have been noted. Granting Parfit’s position, one should move away from practices according to Self-Interest and Common-Sense Morality, and move toward practices of impersonal altruism. 

According to Parfit, Nagel claimed that it is psychologically impossible for us to believe the Reductionist View of personal identity even if it is true. After a thoughtful review of his logic, Parfit cites Buddha as reinforcement for the claim that "it is indeed possible to believe this [Relation R view of personal identity]" (“Psychological View 258).  It is interesting to note, as Andrew May informs, that early on, others recognized the parallels between Parfit’s views and early Buddhist philosophy. May reports  in a book review, that Mark Siderits has recently written Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy, a book that compares and contrasts “Parfitian reductionism” with early and later Buddhist writings. Siderits uses arguments from the later Buddhist writings against the “Parfitian” view (May). Parfit admits that even though he has intellectually accepted his own view, he still has a problem: "But at some lower level I would still be inclined to believe that there must always be a real difference between some future person's being me, and his being someone else" (“Psychological View” 258-9).

Reflecting back on this survey of thought experiments, one must agree with Wittgenstein and Quine, and proclaim that one has not learned much from this use of one's imagination. One must reject Parfit’s analyses, and wait for other vehicles to take one along other paths of reasoning about personal identity. Parfit depends too heavily on his thesis that “the division of a person’s consciousness is in fact possible.” He attempts to eliminate the circularity problem, and to show that personal identity is not what matters, but one sees that his presentation of the My Division case does not adequately meet the challenges. Although he quotes Rawls in saying that the nature of a thing determines its “correct regulative principle,” Parfit goes to great lengths to propose whole different kinds of natures for human beings, based on imaginary reproduction processes. By doing so, he expects one to get rid of one's unhealthy attachment to the importance of one's identity.

Parfit muddies the waters with his extreme science fiction cases. He wants one to adopt language that would make one think in terms of collective living, and eliminate the personal in one's identification. I, for one, will continue along my self-satisfying, individual path, continuing to strive to fulfill my desires and ambitions. Along the way, I will find satisfaction and pleasure among my connections with other persons. The strong connections will be of my choosing, however, and they will not be based on Relation R. Nevertheless, I may come to realize that I am making choices from a deliberative standpoint, as Korsgaard has described. I will still wonder, and be fascinated by the metaphysical problem of personal identity. The final answers to the questions posed by personal identity cannot be found in these kinds of thought experiments. Nevertheless, Parfit and others that have provided creative thought experiments have added many provocative ideas to this conversation.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

WORKS CITED

American Heritage Dictionary, The. 1992 ed. Software by Writing Tools Group, Inc. 1992.

Auman, Robert. "Baby Born with two heads." Catholic Online Forum Discussion Area: The ASK FATHER Question Box. 25 Feb. 2005. 20 Oct. 2005 <http://oldforum.catholic.org/discussion/messages/41/844447.html?1109338199>

Bergmann, Frithjof. "Freedom and the Self." Kolak and Martin 407-421.

Bermϊdez, Josι Luis. "Reduction and the Self." Gallagher and Shear 431-439.

Brook, Andrew. "Unified Consciousness and the Self." Gallagher and Shear 39-47.

"Commissurotomy." The American Heritage Dictionary.

Dennett, Daniel C. Consciousness Explained. New York: Penguin, 1991.

Descartes, Rene. “Meditations.” Descartes: Philosophical Writings. trans. Elizabeth Anscombe and Peter T. Geach. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1971.

Fields, Lloyd. “Parfit on Personal Identity and Desert.” The Philosophical Quarterly  37 (Oct. 1987):  432-440.

Galison, Peter. "Einstein's Compass." Scientific American Spec. issue Sep. 2004: 66-69.

Gallagher, Shaun and Jonathan Shear, eds. Models of The Self. Thorverton: Imprint Academic, 1999.

Gendler, Tamar Szabσ. "Exceptional Persons: On the Limits of Imaginary Cases." Gallagher and Shear 447-465.

Gergen, Kenneth J. "The Social Construction of Self-Knowledge.” Kolak and Martin 372-385.

Gilead, Amihud. “Spinoza’s Principium Individuationis and Personal Identity.” International Studies in Philosophy 15 (1983). 6 Aug. 2007 <http://caute.2084.ru/spinoza/aln/prindiv.htm>

Hobbes, Thomas. "Of Identity and Diversity." Hoy and Oaklander 110-12.

Hoy, Ronald C., and L. Nathan Oaklander, eds. Metaphysics: Classic and Contemporarry Readings. Belmont: Wadsworth, 1991.

Hume, David. "On Identity and Personal Identity."  Hoy and Oaklander 130-37.

Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. trans. Norman Kemp Smith. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1965.

Kolak, Daniel, and Raymond Martin. Self & Identity. New York: Macmillan, 1991

---. “Unity of Consciousness: Introduction.” Kolak and Martin 3-15.

---. "Personal Identity: Introduction." Kolak and Martin 163-180.

Korsgaard, Christine M. "Personal Identity and the Unity of Agency: A Kantian Response to Parfit." Kolak and Martin 323-338.

Leibniz, G. W. “Monadology.” Trans. Robert Latta and Donald Rutherford. 1 Oct. 1999. 6 Aug. 2007 <http://philosophy2.ucsd.edu/~rutherford/Leibniz/modad.htm>

Lin, Martin. “Memory and Personal Identity in Spinoza.” 6 Aug. 2007. <http://individual.utoronto.ca/mtlin/identity.pdf>

Locke, John.  "Of Identity and Diversity."  Hoy and Oaklander 113-23.

Mandik, Pete (May 11, 2004). "Supervenience" in Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind. Ed. C. Eliasmith. Oct. 15, 2005 <http://philosophy.uwaterloo.ca/MindDict/supervenience.html>

Martin, Raymond. "Identity, Transformation, and What Matters in Survival." Kolak and Martin 289-301.

May, Andrew. Rev. of Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy by Mark Siderits. May 2004. 5 Aug. 2007 <http://andrew-may.com/siderits.htm>

Midgley, Mary. "Being Scientific About Our Selves." Gallagher and Shear 467-480.

Nagel, Thomas. "The Self as Private Object." Hoy and Oaklander 179-187.

Oaklander, Nathan. “Parfit, Circularity, and the Unity of Consciousness.” Mind  384 (Oct. 1987): 525-529.

Olson, Eric T. “Personal Identity.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2007 Edition). Ed. Edward N. Zalta. 5 July 2007. <http://plato.standord.edu/archives/spr2007/entries/identity-personal/>

Panksepp, Jaak. "The Periconscious Substrates of Consciousness: Affective States and the Evolutionary Origins of the Self." Gallagher and Shear 113-130.

Parfit, Derek. "Divided Minds and the Nature of Persons." Kolak and Martin 82-88.

---. "The Psychological View." Kolak and Martin 227-266.

---. "Personal Identity, Rationality, and Morality." Kolak and Martin 301-322.

---. "Personal Identity." Hoy and Oaklander 166-178.

---. Reasons and Persons.  New York: Clarendon Press – Oxford, 1984.

Pickering, John. "The Self Is a Semiotic Process." Gallagher and Shear 63-79.

Radden, Jennifer. "Pathologically Divided Minds Synchronic Unity and Models of Self." Gallagher and Shear 343-358.

Rand, Ayn. Atlas Shrugged. New York: Random House, 1957.

Reid, Thomas. "Of Identity and On Mr. Locke's Theory of Personal Identity."  Hoy and Oaklander 124-129.

Robinson, John, “Personal Identity and Survival,” Journal of Philosophy LXXXV.6  (June, 1988): 319-328.

Sass, Louis A. "Schizophrenia, Self-consciousness, and the Modern Mind." Gallagher and Shear 319-341.

Shear, Jonathan. "Experiential Clarification of the Problem of Self." Gallagher and Shear 407-420.

Shoemaker, David. “Personal Identity and Ethics.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2007 Edition). Ed. Edward N. Zalta. 5 July 2007. <http://plato.standord.edu/archives/spr2007/entries/identity-ethics/>

Shoemaker, Sydney. "Survival and the Importance of Identity." Kolak and Martin 267-272.

"Sorites." The American Heritage Dictionary.

Sperry, R. W. "Hemisphere Deconnection and Unity in Conscious Awareness."  Kolak and Martin 55-68.

Stairs, Allen. "Quantum Mechanics, Mind, and Self." Kolak and Martin 453-472.

Unger, Peter. "The Physical View." Kolak and Martin 192-212.

Wilkes, Kathleen. Real People: Personal Identity Without Thought Experiments. New York: Clarendon Press - Oxford; 2001.

Williams, Bernard. "The Self and the Future." Kolak and Martin 181-192.

 

 



[1] commissurotomy - The surgical incision of a commissure of the brain, sometimes used in the treatment of certain psychiatric disorders. commissure – 2.a A tract of nerve fibers passing from one side to the other of the spinal cord or brain. (American Heritage)

[2] supervenience - A set of properties or facts M supervenes on a set of properties or facts P if and only if there can be no changes or differences in M without there being changes or differences in P. "The fact that supervening properties need not be identical to their subvening properties is the source of the great appeal of supervenience to contemporary philosophers of mind who have come to think that the mental cannot be identical to the physical (largely due to considerations of multiple realizability) yet want to be physicalists and thus hold on to the notion that the mental is nonetheless determined by the physical. Thus they subscribe to the thesis of psychophysical supervenience, AKA, the supervenience thesis" (Mandik)

[3] "The Secret Life of the Brain" is a four part series that aired on San Diego's KPBS station in July, 2004. This series is documented on the PBS website with the series home page <http://www.pbs.org/wnet/brain/> (10/16/2004)

[4] An understanding of Rand’s Trader Principle, Rational Egoism, and metaphysical principles are concretely demonstrated throughout her novel Atlas Shrugged.

[5] Baby Born With Two Heads aired on the Discovery Channel in San Diego, California, on October 19, 2005 at 10:00 pm.