Questions/Susan Fleck’s answers: re – Persistence in Personal
Identity presentation (draft paper) © Susan Fleck
Suzi, you summarize some of Parfit's main views about personal
identity, a few of them being "personal identity just consists in physical
and psychological continuity," and that deep chains of psychological
connectedness (called Relation R) "are what counts for [being] a continuous person."
Now, you highlight that Parfit's view on what constitutes
personal identity is considered a reductionist one, meaning that self-identity
can be reduced to a set of criteria that do not depend on/get
their validity from whether or not a "person" or a "unified
identity" actually exists. In other words, our concept of
self-identity is not as determinate or assured as we think; and according to
Parfit, what we believe we have for a personal identity is actually an
impersonal mental continuity of memories and experiences; a linear
psychological chain based on survival
as opposed to an immeasurable and irreducible self based on a unique character.
Parfit’s view of P/I is just the
Relation R, or as you say, linear psychological chain. It is not based on
survival, but survival of the psychology, if it were possible as in the various
experiments, would be more important than strict personal identity, if the
original person were to expire.
One’s Character, to a reductionist, . . . I
would substitute the word ego and say that
Parfit denies that there is an irreducible ego, or soul, apart from the brain
as the carrier of our psychology, memories, intentions, etc.
Parfit states: "It becomes more plausible to claim that, just as
we are right to ignore whether people come from the same or different nations,
we are right to ignore whether experiences comes within the same or different
lives" (Personal Identity,
rationality 321). Christine Korsgaard points out the circularity in
Parfit's theory: "If you begin with the view that a person is a subject of
experiences, and take away the subject, you are indeed left with nothing but
experiences. But you will begin with that view only if you assume from the
start that having experiences is what life is all about" (338).
To strengthen Parfit's view on identity, you bring up the teletransportation
example. Simply put, Parfit thinks that if my body and brain are exactly replicated on Mars
out of new material and my original body and brain are destroyed, then under
the criterion of having a reliable cause/vehicle of continuity, that
replica on Mars would still be ME; since my physical and psychological
components have survived and been copied precisely, the same I still exists on Mars. But
the question is, is it the same ME?
Parfit claims that a person would
continue to exist if his body were annihilated and subsequently perfectly
replicated even if the switch occurred by sheer accident. This claim is
supported by the feeling that
"the switch would be of no practical or emotional significance" and
therefore, the replicated person should continue on the life and be treated as if there had been no switch.
Frederick Doepke argues that we cannot infer whether the same person exists based on our attitudes and feelings, but, more
importantly, he questions the plausibility of the assumed attitudes. Someone
once said to Doepke: "Although we may not care whether our accountant is a
mere replica, we certainly do care in the case of a spouse.” Jomil, you are
demonstrating Doepke’s case!
Is it possible to "replicate" exactly what we are, for
everything we are and are not was caused by moments in time and actual places
in time that can never happen again in the exact same way? Isn't Parfit
discounting the importance of actual past and particular physical environments and
our relations to them in determining the nature--or at least notion--of
personal identity? Are we not relativity and not just continuity;
contextuality and not just replication?
I don’t
think Parfit discounts anything in particular phenomenological experiences. The
physical environment and one’s relationship to that environment at a particular
time would naturally be a part of the context of any experience. His point is
that he thinks we can explain the experience by what is going on in the brain,
including multiple perceptions at any given time, without having to say that
these experiences are owned by a
substantial, or soul-person. I am not sure what you are mean by ‘are we not
relativity,’ but Parfit would say that what a person is is someone who is consciously aware of the continuity and
contiguity of day-to-day experiences, intentions, etc.
The
important part of your question is: “Is it possible to “replicate” exactly what we are . . .?” – there may
be physiological or physics reasons why this is impossible; or, if there is really some further fact involved in personal identity, then that would
preclude the possibility of replication.
Science-fictionally, many of us have seen Captain Kirk beamed up from one place
and transported to another, and in turn, understood that it was the same
Captain Kirk; the same man; the same exact person we saw just before the
transportation. But despite the more plausible real-life cases, I just don't
think Parfit's identity view can hold, or at least I can't grasp it in an
actualized way.
Thomas
Nagel stated: "It is therefore hard to internalize a conception of
myself as identical with my brain: if I am told that my brain is about to be
split, and that the left half will be miserable and the right half euphoric,
there is no form that my subjective expectations can take, because my idea of
myself doesn't allow for divisibility—nor do the emotions of expectation, fear,
and hope" (Self 185-86).
Susan’s further comments: It takes a whole lifetime to be who
one is;
Humeans
would say that who one thinks he or she is,
is a result of constructing a fictitious ego from the resemblances of
contiguity of perceptions.
Daniel
Dennett has a fascinating account of personal identity. A fundamental
difference between humans and other animals is that humans talk. Dennett
reminds us that we use language to present ourselves to others and to
ourselves. He construes that we use words “weaving them like spider-webs into
self-protective strings of narrative.”
Dennett suggests that our fundamental method of self-protection and
self-definition is telling stories and controlling the process as we tell
others about ourselves. Just as spiders do not have to consciously think about
how to spin webs, we do not deliberately construct the narratives we tell
others. These tales are spun by our
consciousness, our narrative selfhood. From these words one speaks, others posit a
unified agent, what Dennett calls a “center
of narrative gravity.” Possible evidence for this theory comes from
Multiple Personality Disorder patients who seem to have multiple selves sharing the same body, each with
a distinct name and separate autobiography.
Dennett reflects on an analogy of a termite colony that accomplishes
such clever projects with no such chief executive (Origins 360-61). To use
another analogy, we personify the USA as if it had an inner self or being. There is no one agency that
embodies all of the qualities of the nation. However, the president, as Head of
State, is meant to represent different parts of the nation to each other, to
advocate a common value system, and to be the spokesperson for the USA in
dealing with other nations. Through the political process, the population,
mostly through the news media, tries out various fictive versions of what they
would consider to be an “ideal president.” Because there is more than one
dominant ideal version, various
candidates tend to mold themselves to these views. In the end, only one
survives the process to become the Head of State and claim the right to speak
for the whole nation (150). An individual human being in an unconscious manner
creates one or more ideal fictive-self and elects
one to become her Head of Mind. The main difference is that in the case of
individuals there is considerable outside influence such as from parents,
friends, and even from enemies. With this analogy, one does not start out with
any definition of “what it means to be me,” but, eventually a version of
selfhood that “makes sense” emerges until one that seems to be “the real me” is
elected.
An enduring concept about consciousness
is that of what Dennett calls a Cartesian Theater which acts like an imagined
control center. This image comes about because of a seemingly unshakable
concept that there is some kind of self
that experiences an experience, one
that imagines a purple cow when
instructed to do so. Most events going on in one's brain are not normally witnessed by anyone, just like events
that go on in other parts of the body are not usually witnessed. But conscious events are, by definition,
witnessed by somebody. Since no
particular part of the brain, such as the pineal gland, is the thinker that
does the thinking, and it does not seem plausible to attribute that role to the
whole brain, these ideas of a self
(or a person or a soul) and of the mind
stuff of consciousness that are distinct from the brain or the body are
deeply rooted in our ways of thinking (28-9).
It is also common to think of vision as
pictures in the mind. Are there mind's eyes to see these pictures? If not, why
would there be pictures in the head?
However, since there is no reason to believe that the brain has any central
headquarters, a view Dennett calls Cartesian
materialism, then an observer's subjective sense of sequence and
simultaneity is determined by something other than "order of
arrival." In order to understand how things like sight and sound become
phenomenologically "centrally available" we are forced to replace the
Cartesian Theater with a new model (107-8). Something like the Cartesian
Theater is in view when neuroscientists and philosophers discuss "the
binding problem" where it is often presupposed that there is some place in
the brain where various discriminations "are put into registration with
each other" such as getting the sound track in sync with visual stimuli,
coloring in shapes and filling in blank spots" (258).
and it took eons multiplied by eons to even have a human
lifetime as we know it.
Dennett:
Through
three evolutionary forms—genetic, phenotypic plasticity, and memetic—human
consciousness has arisen and developed at increasing rates of speed. During the Great Encephalization period,
completed about 150,000 years ago and prior to the development of language and
agriculture, the brains of our hominid ancestors grew is size to be four times
as large as chimpanzee brains. Those brains are comparable to ours in size and
shape. It is now understood that this enormous growth was not a response to
complexities arising from the use of language: brain specialization for
language was a very recent add-on.
The most rapid and remarkable expansion of human mental abilities has taken
place since the end of the last ice age only a mere 10,000 years ago, an
extremely short time in evolutionary terms. Since we were born with brains
containing very few if any additional powers compared to brains 10,000 years
ago, then the tremendous advances in culture must be due to, according to
Dennett, "harnessing the plasticity of that brain in radically new ways—by
creating something like software to
enhance its underlying powers" (189-90). Thus, cultural evolution and the
transmission of its products through the medium of memes have enabled humans to use the plasticity of their brains not
just about how to learn, but to learn how to learn better. A meme is a unit of cultural transmission,
like an idea, a tune, or a way of making something, that propagate themselves
from brain to brain through a process of imitation or by learning things from
others. (Dennett reports that Richard Dawkins coined the term meme.)
This is the second new medium of evolution (193-208).
Nevertheless, the computer analogy is
"tantalizingly suggestive" to Dennett for these reasons that he has
postulated: consciousness (1) is too recently engendered to be hard-wired
within the brain; (2) is a product of
cultural evolution that gets ingrained in brains through training; (3) is
successfully installed through innumerable microsettings within the plasticity
of the brain; and (4) creates the user
illusion derived from the various data inputs from the senses
(201-20). (review more of Dennett’s
theory.)
Dennett cites philosopher Robert van
Gulick to bolster the conception of the self that Dennett is providing: “I, the
personal subject of experience, do understand. I can make all the necessary
connections within experience, calling up representations to immediately
connect one with another. The fact that my ability is the result of my being
composed of an organized system of subpersonal components which produce my
orderly flow of thoughts does not impugn my ability. What is illusory or
mistaken is only the view that I am some distinct substantial self who produces
these connections in virtue of a totally non-behavioral form of understanding.”
Susan Fleck:
Most arguments I have found in the literature are narrow
views based upon one methodology, a limited set of case examples, and usually
constrained by an assumptive metaphysical world view such as materialism or
reductionism. The methods I have encountered in my readings are: (1) Thought
experiments using imaginary cases; (2) Real unusual human case studies; (3)
Introspection; (4) Phenomenology; (5) Simple meditation; (6) Disciplined
meditation based on various eastern methods that take years of practice; (7)
Psychological experiments and studies of dissociation cases like multiple
personality disorder; (8) Scientific cognitive studies and quantum mechanics
theory.
In thinking about highly abstract conceptual questions such
as is there really a God? or really personal identity? philosophers
should be going through a rigorous analysis using a procedure such as is
explained in the logic textbook Thinking With Concepts. Perhaps framework
is not a good word for what I would like to see. I am looking for a
comprehensive overview and analyses of all major theories and viewpoints on
personal identity. The analyses would include examining these questions about
each theory: What are the strengths and weaknesses of the methodology used to
come to conclusions? What are the assumptions about the metaphysics underlying
the viewpoint? What are the implications
of the account? And what can be learned when one attempts to apply various
types of puzzle cases within a specific paradigm of personal identity. It would be interesting to see if one could
synthesize some of the viewpoints by doing such a study.
My concept of personal identity is eclectic, borrowing on
the notions of various philosophers and traditions. I could take the easy way
out and identify with Socrates and simply say ‘I don’t know the answer’ and
continue to be a gadfly by examining others’ methodologies and conclusions,
posing questions that need further answers. It is true that I don’t know, but I do have my own conceptual
framework. Time does not permit a full explanation, as that could fill another
several hours, so I can only give you a brief skeleton. Since I have not come
to any definitive metaphysical conclusions, I agree with the Kantian position
Christine Korsgaard argues for: ““I . . . have reasons for regarding
myself as the same rational agent as the one who will occupy my body in the
future.” I believe myself to be a unified agent based on practical grounds,
even though there are conflicting desires and beliefs in my psychology. My
unity is implicit in the standpoint
from which I choose; I deliberate as if
there was a unified ‘I’ that expresses my will
and ultimately chooses how to act. I also agree with Husserl that our self is much more than a mere biological
animal entity. The foundation for a sense of self for Husserl lies in one’s
sphere of ownness, a sphere that requires a distinction from all that is alien.
This kind of self is more than a ‘thinking principle,’ and more than a living
organism. Along with one’s perceptions and sensations, one has the power to
govern within one’s sphere of ownness. As such, then, a self is a
psycho-physical unity.
If you would like to put a label on my view of personal
identity, you can call me a Postmodern, Existential, Buddhist, Randian, who
subscribes to the philosophy of Science of Mind in the form that the Church of
Religious Science teaches. I said I was eclectic!! In a nutshell, I believe
that there is a deep further fact to
our identity; I have just not figured out exactly what that fact is or how it works; nor do I ever expect to. This belief is grounded in a
metaphysical viewpoint that says that Aristotle’s Prime Mover, or God, is a
combination of Pure Energy, Pure Intelligence, and Pure Consciousness. What
else could have started the Big Bang and the material universe, and individuation,
and provided for all natural laws, and enabled forms of life to evolve? The
atheist viewpoint can only be ‘it just happened.’ And now, we humans have evolved
to not only partake in consciousness, but also self-consciousness. What happens to our essential consciousness-mind-soul after we die? Does our identity
end there at the death of our brain and body? Does our further fact essence get enfolded into the ONE in a Spinozean
manner? Is our individuality preserved such that we go to some different
universal plane?
That is just one aspect that would need to be addressed
when trying out my concept within the framework of a comprehensive analysis on
this subject. I will have lots of problems addressing many of the cases apart
from ‘normal’ human beings. Once I have figured all of that out, I will
probably be able to answer the question, ‘what is the meaning of life?’