Persistence in Personal Identity:
Parfit and Science
Fiction Puzzles
© Susan
Fleck
Introduction
Most people, either consciously or implicitly, have a commonsense belief
that they each constitute a unified self.
David Hume reflects that some philosophers think that we cannot be certain of
anything if we doubt the "perfect identity and simplicity" of our own
continuing existence (131). However, based upon the numerous and diverse
theories about personal identity found in the literature, one realizes that
such a commonsense belief is in itself an unarticulated speculative theory. I
propose a broader framework approach to this problem; one that is more
comprehensive in scope than any I have found in the literature. This would
include analyzing modern views about models of the self, real human puzzle cases including human oddities, paranormal
phenomena and religious beliefs; science fiction thought experiments, and
puzzle cases from science fiction literature.
This presentation is about the use of science fiction thought
experiments to substantiate views about Personal Identity. There will be some contrasts
and comparisons from other science fiction venues weaved in alongside these
philosophical experiments. The moral and ethical implications from Derek Parfit’s account are far reaching and revolutionary.
Because he is influential in these debates, I focus on Parfit's
views. You will see how he bolsters his claims that identity can be a matter of
degrees and that survival is more important than identity. Although I am critical of
this methodology of basing conclusions solely on logical conclusions from these
kinds of experiments, they certainly provide food for thought and have a place
in a broader framework for debates
about personal identity. Before presenting these experiments and other sci-fi
examples, I will provide a brief outline, history, and
importance of the problem.
What is the Personal Identity Problem?
Those who are doing research in Personal Identity are working
on one or more of the following eight questions: (1) Who
am I? This is a question about one’s individual psychological identity and how
this changes over time. (2) What is necessary and sufficient for something to
be counted as a person? For example,
can an ovum or embryo, or someone in a vegetative state, be considered a
person? (3) The Persistence question asks: What are the necessary and
sufficient criteria for personal identity to obtain for a person to be the same person over time. This is different
from the Evidence question: (4) What evidence determines
whether the same person here now (say in the courtroom) is the one who was at a
specific place yesterday? (5) The Population question asks how many people are
there at a certain place at a certain time? What does that number signify? Could a human
being with a split personality be considered two persons? (6) What am I,
metaphysically speaking? Am I merely a biological animal, or essentially an
immaterial soul, or bundles of perceptions, or the bearer of a historical
narrative, or some combination of these things? (7) How could I have been different than I actually am, say if I would have
had different parents? (8) What is important about the fact of my identity or
my persistence? Can survival be separated from identity and can that be more
important?[1] This presentation focuses on the Persistence
Problem which entails also addressing the question about the nature of humans: What am I?
Brief history of the Persistence
problem
Following is a very brief history for putting the modern debates in
context.
René Descartes’ dictum commonly known as “I think, therefore I am” was
derived from his thought experiment in which he was determined to doubt
everything he believed up to that point. He could doubt that he had a body but
not that he was thinking. His view of the self was that it exists as a
consciousness continuing throughout one’s awareness.[2] This Cartesian
view espouses that a person is essentially a non-physical substance, or
soul. The current form of this view has evolved away from Descartes’ theory and
is now often called the Ego Theory,
or transcendental view, whereby a person continues to exist as an Ego, a subject of experience.[3] Other moderns claim
that personal identity consists of some further
fact, not necessarily a soul, but other than merely a body and/or a brain.
John Locke originated the important relational
view and memory criterion for personal identity; that it consists in not bodily identity, but rather relations that
obtain among present conscious memories and the earlier experiences or actions
remembered. Locke was
the first one to use thought experiments for this problem and the first to
explicitly connect personal identity with ethical concerns. For example, he
poses the possibility of a prince having his soul, which contains his consciousness-memories,
transferred to a cobbler’s body and vice versa. Locke claims that everyone
would agree that the body of the cobbler would then be the same person of the prince, accountable only
for the prince’s actions. However, he thinks that no one would say that it
would be the same man. He is clearly
making a distinction between being a person
and being a human being.
A similar example of Locke’s prince and pauper exchange is found in the
1988 movie big in which a young boy
makes a wish at a fairground machine to be big. To his amazement, he wakes up
the following morning to find out that his body now looks like a thirty year
old man, played by Tom Hanks. However, he is still a kid and continues to act
like a twelve year old boy. [4] This movie illustrates
the importance of the body in how others perceive one’s self as a human, and how they expect one to act,
even though the person inside that
body has the memories and psychological makeup of who he was before the drastic
change in the body.
Locke thought that what we call our self
is that person who is a continuing same intelligent agent and that the self is a forensic term that applies to
one’s actions and their merit. With his view the justice of reward and
punishment as well as one’s desire to be concerned primarily with one’s own
life is founded upon the personal identity of one’s consciousness.[5] This thinking is the foundation for one of
the dominant theories in ethics, that of self-interest. Locke has been called
the father of the personal identity problem, because for a long time most
thinkers who wrote on this subject were responding to him.
Joseph Butler took exception to having personal identity become separated
from both biological and substance-soul identity. He called Locke’s notion a “wonderful
mistake” because Locke failed to recognize the circularity of his thoughts.
Consciousness-memory presupposes
identity and therefore cannot constitute it. A memory of an experience is not
what makes it mine; I am able to
remember it because it is already
mine. Butler’s view is that these are experiences of a substance that constitutes me now.[6]
One might say that David Hume is the father of logical construction
theories for personal identity. In contrast with the Cartesian view of a substantial self,
Hume offers the Bundle view which accounts
for our concept of self in terms of bundles of experiences that are connected
by the logical relationships of contiguity and resemblances of our perceptions .[7] On Hume's view, one mistakes what is merely a bundle of
perceptions for a self as a
perceiver. We merely construct a concept of an ego, or a self, in our minds
based on the connections we make from these various perceptions.
Immanuel Kant agreed with Descartes in that inner experience is extended
in time, and outer experience is extended in space as well as in time. On the
other hand Kant agreed with Hume in that one could not derive an overall principle of unity, or any definite concept
of a necessarily inferred unitary self, from the content of one's experiences.
Instead, Kant called such an overall unity "the transcendental unity of
apperception." The self, according to Kant, can only be known as an
abstraction, a "something=X." Because both Descartes and Hume were
right in that the self is both absolutely necessary and at the same time
vacuous and ungraspable, Kant muses that this paradox "mocks and torments"
men.[8]
Even though Kant's theory of a transcendental self still has influence,
it accounts for personal identity by appealing to such substances which focuses
such an inquiry outside the bounds of both experience and science. Contemporary
theorists usually work within the context of relational views. They use complex types of memory and psychological
relationships in their neo-Humean theories. Reductionist
accounts of identity are still Lockean in that
personal identity consists in overlapping chains of continuity and
psychological connectedness that hold strongly from a day to day basis. Parfit’s theory is Reductionist; you will see later more
fully what that means. The contemporary debates gained momentum with Parfit’s early 1970s articles.
Why is this problem important?
The topic is still very much alive and heavily debated in our
contemporary world. There are investigations about personal identity within the
areas of psychology, metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics. This discussion
focuses about how important personal identity theory is in relationship to
moral theory. One could argue that one's belief about personal identity is implicit
in whatever moral theory that one adopts.
Many object to the disunifying implications from reductionist accounts
like Parfit’s. Some assert that identity accounts
must be constrained by ethical considerations. In other words, if an identity
theory disrupts what one perceives to be the right moral theory, then that identity account needs to be tossed
out. This begs the question about which is the right moral theory upon which to base personal identity theory. We
still have good reason to maintain that ethics depends on the metaphysics.[9] In any case, most people working on this
problem seem to be in agreement regarding the important relationship between
personal identity and ethics. Currently, a fundamental assumption in social
science, law and theology is the notion of the enduring identity of individual
persons to which legal and moral responsibility can be attached. One can only
ponder the implications of the possibility that philosophy would discover that
the enduring self is an erroneous
notion. What kind of impact would such a finding have on our legal and moral
institutions?[10]
Parfit declares his agenda to
refute the Self-interest Theory by targeting and dismantling two commonly held
beliefs. The first belief is about the nature
of personal identity that holds that in all cases the question about identity
must be determinate. With this view, one must be able to definitively know whether one would exist or not
given any scenario of future events that may befall one. For example, if I were
to wake up tomorrow with total amnesia, will I, the person yesterday,
still exist? The second commonly held belief is that if the question about
identity is indeterminate, then we
are unable to answer related important questions such as those about survival,
memory, and responsibility.[11] Parfit asserts that
he will convince us to change our view about the nature of personal identity
and that this should persuade us "to change our beliefs about rationality,
and about morality."[12] He stresses the
strong relationship between these themes in quoting Rawls, who said that “the
correct regulative principle for anything depends upon the nature of that thing.”[13]
Parfit thinks his view liberates one from morose feelings
resulting from thinking about one's eventual demise. One will see how adopting
his account of personal identity enables one to be more impartial and to move
away from Self-Interest and toward impersonal rational altruism. For example,
he is a proponent for these wide-sweeping social changes: a distribution of
wealth; paternalistic government intervention to prevent great imprudence by individuals; a legal distinction between
persons and humans, thus enabling the killing of humans via abortion and
euthanasia; and less punishment the further away from a crime a convict is with
respect to his psychological connections in regard to the crime.[14]
Necessary and Sufficient Criteria: Using Thought
Experiments
Proposed solutions to the Persistence Question fall into one of three
categories, or types of criteria necessary for personal identity to obtain.
With the Psychological Approach, you are the future being that inherits its
mental features such as memories, beliefs, desires, etc., from you, and you are
that past being whose mental features you inherited. There is dispute about
whether these mental features must be underpinned by the physical continuity of
the body or brain. The second approach claims that whether or not you survive
has nothing to do with psychological facts; rather, your body must survive.
(This should not be confused with the Evidence Question that deals with finding
out who is who.) The third view, called the Simple View, denies that something, either body or mental
continuity, is necessary for identity to persist through time: something other
than itself. This is often combined, but not necessarily, with the view that we
are immaterial (with souls) and have no parts.[15]
Thought experiments are used in an attempt to tease apart physical
structures from psychological structures in order to determine what constitutes
necessary criteria for personal identity. With such cases, one can posit that
either the physical structures are preserved while the psychological ones are
disrupted or vice versa, and then determine whether or not personal identity is
preserved or not as a result of the experiment.[16]
Parfit thinks that our
current false beliefs about ourselves
and what persons are can be best
brought to light through the use of science fiction imaginary cases. He
acknowledges that others have questioned whether he exceeds the effective
limits of this method. He proclaims justification in that we can discover the
nature of personal identity because "these cases arouse in most of us
strong beliefs."[17] One can argue,
however, that religious sermons and stories also produce among listeners strong
reactions and beliefs about our human nature; beliefs that usually subscribe to
some form of the transcendental, or ego, view of personal identity.
Parfit admits that most of
his cases are either "merely
technically" impossible or that they contravene the laws of nature and
are therefore "deeply"
impossible. This does not matter, he claims, if the question of what one is
trying to show is structured properly. "But," Parfit
cautions, ". . . depending on our question, impossibility may make some thought-experiment
irrelevant."[18]
We will proceed to look at some of these
experiments to see if he and others heed this advice and to see what strong
beliefs are aroused in us.
Sci-Fi Thought Experiments and Parfit’s Personal Identity Account
He sets the stage for changing the debate by changing one of the central
questions. Instead of focusing on the question 'Under what condition is your
personal identity preserved?' he asks 'Under what conditions is what matters
primarily to you in survival preserved?' The importance of personal identity
was called into question through the use of thought experiments involving
hypothetical fission cases in which one person splits into two new qualitatively
identical persons who are also qualitatively identical to the original person.
Sydney Shoemaker claims that if I were given two options for having my
healthy half-brain transplanted into another body that is healthy, I should
choose the less risky procedure whereby my cancer ridden half-brain and body
would be destroyed after the
operation. With this option, it would mean for certain that my identity will
not carry forward onto the recipient person because two persons cannot have the
same identity at one time. The more risky process entails first destroying my
diseased half-brain and then transplanting the other half: then the recipient
person would have no "competitor" at any time for the status of being
me, and therefore, she could count as
me. However, I should choose the less
risky procedure because in a case like this survival
is more important than identity.[19]
Shoemaker then describes the fission case (also called the My Division case). This case involves a
car wreck of identical triplets where my body is destroyed but my brain is
intact, and my siblings’ brains were destroyed but their bodies were not. My
healthy brain is halved and then transplanted successfully
into my siblings’ bodies. Even if I realize that neither recipient person will
be me because there can not be duplication in identity, nevertheless, I should not consider this procedure as
impending death. Instead, assuming that the psychological continuity criteria
of personal identity is a correct view, I should have an attitude toward my two
successor persons essentially like I would normally have about my own future
delights, successes and failures under normal circumstances.[20]
Parfit maintains that “[. . .] to be a person, a being must be self-conscious,
aware of its identity and its continued existence over time.” His
reductionist view begins with the notion that “personal identity just consists
in physical and psychological continuity.”
Parfit expands Locke’s memory-consciousness
concept such that psychological continuity occurs when we have an “overlapping
chain of experience-memories,” and he adds other psychological components such
as intentions and desires. We may have thousands of direct psychological
connections between who we are today (X) and who we were yesterday (Y). But
there may only be a few connections between who we are today and who we were
twenty years ago. These overlapping chains of psychological components
throughout one’s life are what counts
for a continuous person. This expanded Lockean view
gives us Parfit’s Psychological Criterion, or deep psychological connectedness
(hereafter called Relation R).[21]
There are three versions of this criterion based on what is the right kind of cause of continuity: the Narrow
version stipulates that it must be the normal
cause; it can be any reliable cause
with the Wide version; and any cause under the Widest version. Using Parfit’s simple Teletransportation example, let us say that I enter a teletransporter whereby my body and brain are exactly replicated on Mars out of new
material and my original body and brain are destroyed. Under the Narrow version
the replica on Mars would not be me
because the continuance was not due to a normal cause. A normal cause would be
if I were transported to Mars and landed there in some spaceship. It would be
me, however, under the two Wide formulae. Why should it matter whether this brain and body gets to Mars? The
natural fear, Parfit construes, is that, according to
most peoples’ belief, only that condition within a Narrow cause will ensure that I
get to Mars.[22]
However, those of us who enjoyed hearing Captain Kirk in Star Trek constantly
imploring “Beam me up Scottie” thought that the Kirk who was in immediate
danger on some planet was the same
Kirk who almost instantly reappeared in the transporter room. And he did not
get there by any narrow cause.
In another experiment, Parfit imagines that the
teletransporter malfunctions such that my body and
brain are not destroyed on earth, yet there is an identical duplicate made of
me that is now on Mars. This is an example of a branching form of an experiment whereby the result is two
qualitatively and psychologically identical persons. Personal identity does not
obtain in cases where there are duplicates because two people cannot be the same person even though they share the
same psychology. How weird would that be for you to talk to your duplicate on
Mars? Something similar happens to Captain Kirk in the Star Trek episode The Enemy Within. The transporter
malfunctions and it splits Kirk into two selves who have interactions with each
other, even fighting with each other. In this case the Relation R did not carry forward to Kirk’s doppelganger from the
original Kirk in an identical fashion.[23]
Parfit admits that it is a
logical truth that we can only remember our
own experiences. In order to get around this
logical truth and Butler’s circularity objection, he develops a wider
relational theory of personal identity using concepts called q, or quasi-relationships such as quasi-memory. On this account,
our ordinary memories of past events
become a sub-class of quasi-memories. Even though we do not quasi-remember others’ experiences, we might be able to do so if science could find a way to create a copy
of another’s memory-trace within one’s brain. Parfit
thinks he has met Butler’s challenge. He now reduces
his criteria for personal identity in claiming that “personal identity just
consists in the holding of Relation R.”[24]
Spock of Star Trek fame employed another way to have these quasi-relationships: he used the Vulcan
mind fusion whereby his consciousness would merge with another’s consciousness
such that the thoughts and emotions were shared by Spock and the person or creature
he melded with.[25] Parfit recounts the
My Division case: The resultant two
people would have to acknowledge that right after such an operation they have
only q-memories, q-intentions, etc., of the third person whose half brain they now
each possess.[26]
We can imagine a case like this, Parfit claims,
because it is factually true that one brain hemisphere is enough for survival
in cases of some stroke and other brain injury cases where one loses the
function of one hemisphere.[27]
It was pointed out that Parfit’s analysis still
remains circular if one's q-memory is
of one's own past experience if and only if there are numerous other q-memories of one's own earlier experiences. To meet this objection, Parfit
needs to explain the unity of consciousness, i.e., what unifies simultaneous
experiences into one and the same person.[28] Parfit responds
that one can describe the relations between many experiences and those
relations to a person’s brain without considering that these experiences are had, or owned, by a person.[29] With this view, in the brain at any instant
in time there is merely a single
state of awareness of simultaneous experiences.[30] For Reductionists, nothing more is involved
in unity of consciousness.
The empirical evidence Parfit uses to make this point is actual cases where
surgeons have performed commissurotomies[31] by cutting the
fibers connecting the two upper hemispheres of the brain in order to reduce the
severity of fits of epileptic patients. A side effect of the operation, according
to various tests, is the creation of “two separate spheres of consciousness.” If
it were not possible to divide a person’s consciousness into two separate
streams, Parfit supposes that this impossibility
would support the notion of an indivisible Cartesian Ego. Using the My Division thought experiment, Parfit declares the brain as an unfit bearer of personal
identity and that personal identity is
not what matters.[32] Parfit acknowledges
that he has to make many assumptions to make My Division work, such as both hemispheres have full range of
capabilities, and he admits that this case will probably never be possible.[33] Others have pointed
out facts about brain physiology that make Parfit’s
claims about the importance of commissurotomy
patients unjustified.
Nevertheless, what Parfit wants to accomplish
with the My Division thought
experiment is that the answer to the question ‘which person, if either, will be
me?’ is indeterminate to a Reductionist. It is irrational, to a Reductionist,
to regard the prospect of division in the triplet's case as death. Likewise,
one should be glad that in My Division,
one’s Relation R continues on in two
separate persons, somewhat like having doubled one’s life span. One can say
that neither of the resultant people will be identical to the original and that
the original person is about to die. But, one can state that one survives in terms of Relation R as two different people. Whereas
identity is an all-or-nothing relation, relations that matter in survival are
relations of degree. Parfit proclaims: "If we
ignore this, we shall be led into quite ill-grounded attitudes and beliefs."[34]
Now, let us see how Parfit attempts to
demonstrate that questions about identity can be empty questions with no determinate answer. He introduces the Physical Spectrum case to counter one of
the physical criterion views that holds that as long as my physical brain continues to exist and to be the
brain of a living person then I shall be
that person even if there would be no
psychological connections between who I am now and who I would be later. For
example: Do you think that Ronald Reagan was the same person right before he died with an advanced stage of Alzheimers disease as the person who was the U.S. President in the 1980s? The answer to this
depends upon one’s concept of person
versus human, and one’s views about
personal identity.
In the Physical Spectrum case
there are 100 possible operations to be performed. In a case at the near end,
scientists replace 1% of one’s brain and 1% of one’s body with material made of
new organic matter which contains copies of one's own cells. Near the far end,
99%, and at the farthest end, one’s complete body and brain are replaced only after
they are first destroyed and a replica is made at a later time. At the farthest
end of this spectrum, one sees that there is no physical continuity. He
realizes that most of the far end cases will remain impossible, but that is irrelevant
since one is testing only what one believes about such cases. If one continues to believe that one’s
identity must be determinate, then one must therefore believe that somewhere
along the spectrum there is a sharp borderline where one ceases to exist. . . .
This arbitrary decision cannot justify any claim about what matters.
Reductionism entails that, in some cases, questions about personal identity are
indeterminate and that they are empty questions.[35]
Some physicists would point out a
flaw in the notion that if you were able to make an atom-for-atom copy of
something, then the replicated object will be an exact duplicate of the
original at all levels. Quantum
mechanics discloses that this thesis is false "even for a single pair of electrons.” This has to do with supervenience
theory, something beyond the scope of this presentation.[36] Others claim that psychological properties
supervene upon physiological properties and that explaining survival involves
understanding the properties, the facts,
over and above those about psychological continuity and connectedness.[37]
These objections are illustrated in the Sci-Fi comedy Multiplicity starring Michael Keaton as
Doug Kinney and Andie MacDowell as his wife Laurel who has no clue as to why
her life is falling apart during this adventure. For the philosophers in the
audience, this movie also demonstrates Plato’s Theory of Forms. Overworked and
always overscheduled as a contractor, Doug never has enough time for his wife
and family or for himself. A geneticist offers Doug a solution to this problem:
cloning. The geneticist ‘xeroxes’ Doug and Doug has
to keep this a secret from his wife. However, Doug #2 who takes care of the
contracting business is much more macho than Doug #1. Doug #2 needs someone to
take care of his apartment and Doug #1’s wife, so he gets himself cloned. Doug #3 represents the feminine side of Doug #1.
Doug #3 feels he too needs help, so this copy of a copy gets cloned. Well, Doug
#4 is a disaster, a total imbecile. This goes to prove that a copy is not quite
‘as good’ as the original, and that copies of copies are further degraded.
Now let us look at additional cases Parfit
provides in order to prove identity is indeterminate and a matter of degrees.[38] These experiments
involve human reproduction. Another purpose these cases fulfill is an attempt
to create metaphysical links among persons such that we would be led to believe
that impersonal altruism is a higher moral code than Self-Interest.
There is the Fusion Case: What would it mean if two people were to fuse into
one, such that the resulting person would q-remember
the lives of the two former individuals? Those who regard survival as a matter
of all-or-nothing would regard this as death for the two beginning persons. Parfit recognizes the challenges presented by such a
prospect as this. How would the characteristics and desires of the former
individuals get blended? Nevertheless, he maintains that “only the very
self-satisfied would think of this as death.” This case brings up other questions. What
would society be like if this were possible? Would there be marriages or family
structures? What would they be like? Even if this fusion process were a
plausible possibility to consider, would anyone feel confident about the
outcome of such a fusion?
In the Natural Division case, one
is to imagine beings that would divide into two separate persons, much like an
amoeba divides. One can envision an inversion of a family tree structure
diagram, with one, Eve, at the root and branching off into several generations
of future, seemingly exactly similar,
persons. For Parfit, survival and relationships with
one's ‘past selves’ and ‘future selves’ should be treated as relations of
degrees.
We can contrast this method of reproduction with that of the Tribbles in
the Star Trek episode “The Trouble with Tribbles.” When charmed by the purring
ball of fluff, Uhura takes a Tribble back to the Enterprise. McCoy learns that Tribbles
are asexual and born pregnant and that the more they eat the more they
multiply. And that, my friends, is a recipe for disaster.
Now, put Parfit’s two new processes together
and imagine the Fusion and Division
case; another type of human whereby one reproduces by fusing every autumn and
then divides every spring. This would make a human a kind of everlasting being
in which psychological relations would hold only over limited periods of time.
It is entirely a matter of choice whether, when talking about any of these
persons along the fusion-division chain, one would say “I”, “one of my future selves,”
or “a descendant self.”
He admits that one's belief that identity
is what matters is hard to vanquish, especially in light of discussions about
problem cases that actually occur; cases like ones involving amnesia or brain
damage. Nevertheless, he considers that the My
Division case produces a breach in this belief and, therefore, the
remaining certainty should be easy to topple.[39]
Conclusion: Using Science Fiction for
the Personal Identity Problem
There are three main criticisms others have put forth about using science
fiction thought experiments to determine necessary and sufficient criteria for
personal identity. (1) Some series of cases can be interpreted to bolster the
physical criteria while the same series is used to argue for psychological
criteria;[40]
(2) The philosophers who use this method seem to know little, or care little,
about biology and physiology; and (3) Judgments should not be made based on
stories describing how the world might
become other than how it is currently configured. With this kind of experiment
the relative background about how society would be structured in a certain
scenario is too ambiguous to know whether any given conclusion is clearly
established.[41]
One can argue that using real human cases such as fetuses, amnesia, Alzheimer’s
disease, insanity, fugues, hypnosis, multiple personality, and others are more
interesting and productive in this debate; and that the everyday proverb that
truth is stranger than fiction seems correct in this venue.
By looking only through the lens of science fiction thought experiments,
one may begin to adopt Hume's skeptical despair over coming to any adequate
account of the self and personal identity. Nevertheless, Parfit
and other philosophers, and the many science fiction characters and plots in
literature, have provided creative and provocative ideas to this conversation. These
experiments and fictional stories do have a place within a broader framework of
concepts by which one attempts to understand the nature of human beings and
whether there are real metaphysical underpinnings to personal identity.
I will conclude this discussion by briefly giving a few other examples
from popular Sci-Fi to demonstrate the value this genre adds to debates about various
personal identity questions.
In the Star Trek, Next Generation episode “The Measure of a Man,” a
commander wants to disassemble Data in order to find out how to make more
androids for Starfleet’s use. Data protests and thus a dramatic courtroom drama
unfolds whereby Captain Picard defends Data’s rights as a sentient, intelligent
being who is also a machine. The most dramatic moment in this trial occurs when
Riker, who was assigned to be the prosecutor, simply switches Data off to
demonstrate Data’s inability to achieve self-determination. Consider Doctor,
the emergency medical hologram in the form of a man in The Voyager Star Trek
series. This hologram experienced ongoing evolution of its being due to his adaptive programming. His evolving nature enabled
him to learn how to turn himself off, showing a great deal of independence. Then
there is HAL in 2001: A Space Oddyssey. Who can deny that HAL had great intelligence
and that he displayed feelings when Dave began to unplug HAL’s circuitry one by
one? If humans are able to create such androids as Data, holograms like Doctor,
and computers like HAL, what should be their place and their use in our
society? Would they to be considered persons?
What about the practice of cryonics where people bank on the hope that
one’s deceased body can be frozen and stored until some future time when
medical science would be able to cure whatever caused the death. The prospect
of this can create the phenomenon of time travel. Imagine coming back to life,
say, three hundred years from now. Just think of the psychological displacement
that might be involved in trying to figure out the ‘who am I’ question after
landing in a far away time zone. Various Star Trek episodes involving time
travel and the movie trilogy Back To The Future show what troubles brew when one messes
with one’s place in the history of time.
Lastly, consider Seven of Nine and the Borg in the Star Trek Voyager
series. I doubt whether the Borg is what Derek Parfit
has in mind in order to move us toward more collective living. For
philosophers, the Borg represents a classic example of the One and the Many problem of individuation. The Borg Queen, who is the
central locus of the Borg Collective, has a unique personality and sense of
individuality that other Borg drones are not allowed. However, for her, the
concepts “I” and “we” are interchangeable as she declares that she is the “one
who is many.” It is not clear how she gets replicated and replaced when she
dies in various episodes.[42] The Borg is a
civilization that Starfleet does want
to destroy for the very reason that its voracious appetite to assimilate
individuals from all other civilizations is destroying individuality and
diversity per se. A doctor was able to extract eighty-two percent of Seven of
Nine’s Borg hardware implants. In the episode “The Gift” she demanded to be
returned to the Borg Collective. However, Captain Janeway
was determined to make her fully human again. Seven of Nine’s life history of
first being human, then transformed into a Borg drone, then back into almost
fully human is a great Sci-Fi puzzle case for exploring what are the necessary
and sufficient criteria for personal identity to obtain.
ENDNOTES (to be cross referenced with
Works Cited for full reference)
[1] E. Olson, Chapter 1
[2] Descartes 66 ff., 121
[3] Parfit Divided Minds 83-84
[4] http://www.imdb.com/title/tt0094737/plotsummary (The 1988 movie BIG) (January 18, 2008)
[5] Locke Personal Identity 120-2
[6] D. Shoemaker, Chapter 1
[7] Shear Experiential 408
[8] Kant 329 ff.; Shear Experiential 408-9
[9] David Shoemaker, Chaper 3
[10] John Pickering 74-75
[11] Parfit Personal Identity 167
[12] Parfit Psychological View 261
[13] qtd. in Parfit, Reasons 336
[14] Parfit, Reasons. Documentation for these positions is provided in my thesis.
[15] E. Olson Chapter 3
[16] Kolak and Martin, Personal Identity Introduction 169
[17] Parfit Psychological View 228
[18] Parfit Psychological View 235
[19] Sydney Shoemaker 271
[20] S. Shoemaker 272
[21] Parfit, Psychological View 229-232
[22] Parfit, Psychological View 232, 263
[23] IMDB: http://www.startrek.com/startrek/view/series/TOS/episode/68738.html
[24] Parfit, Psychological View 235-237
[25] http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Spock#Mind_meld (January 18, 2008)
[26] Parfit, Personal Identity 171-2
[27] Parfit, Psychological View 252-3
[28] N. Oaklander, 526-7
[29] Parfit, Reasons 214-7
[30] Parfit, Reasons 250-51
[31] commissurotomy - The surgical incision of a commissure of the brain, sometimes used in the treatment of certain psychiatric disorders. commissure – 2.a A tract of nerve fibers passing from one side to the other of the spinal cord or brain. (American Heritage)
[32] Parfit, Reasons 255, Divided Minds 88
[33] Parfit, Psychological View 253, 256
[34] Parfit, Reasons 258, 265; Personal Identity 168-9, 172
[35] Parfit, Reasons 234
[36] Stairs, 467-8
[37] J. Robinson 328
[38] Parfit, Personal Identity 172-5
[39] Parfit, Personal Identity 170
[40] T. Gendler 458-9
[41] K. Wilkes 2, 8, 19
[42] www.startrek.com site: “The Borg Queenorq Queen.”
WORKS CITED
"Commissurotomy." The American Heritage Dictionary.
Descartes, Rene. “Meditations.” Descartes: Philosophical Writings. trans. Elizabeth Anscombe and Peter T. Geach. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1971.
Gallagher, Shaun and Jonathan Shear, eds. Models of The Self. Thorverton: Imprint Academic, 1999.
Gendler, Tamar Szabó. "Exceptional Persons: On the Limits of Imaginary Cases." Gallagher and Shear 447-465.
Hoy,
Ronald C., and L. Nathan Oaklander, eds. Metaphysics: Classic and Contemporarry Readings.
Hume, David. "On Identity and Personal Identity." Hoy and Oaklander 130-37.
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. trans. Norman Kemp Smith. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1965.
Kolak, Daniel, and Raymond Martin. Self & Identity.
Locke, John. "Of Identity and Diversity." Hoy and Oaklander 113-23.
Oaklander, Nathan. “Parfit, Circularity, and the Unity of Consciousness,” Mind, Vol. 384 (Oct. 1987): pp. 525-529.
Olson, Eric T. “Personal Identity.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2007 Edition). Ed. Edward N. Zalta. 5 July 2007. <http://plato.standord.edu/archives/spr2007/entries/identity-personal/>
Parfit, Derek. "Divided Minds and the Nature of Persons." Kolak and Martin 82-88.
---. "The Psychological View." Kolak and Martin 227-266.
---. "Personal Identity, Rationality, and Morality." Kolak and Martin 301-322.
---. "Personal Identity." Hoy and Oaklander 166-178.
---. Reasons and Persons. New York: Clarendon Press – Oxford, 1984.
Pickering, John. "The Self Is a Semiotic Process." Gallagher and Shear 63-79.
Robinson, John, “Personal Identity and Survival,” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. LXXXV Number 6 (June, 1988): pp. 319-328.
Shear, Jonathan. "Experiential Clarification of the Problem of Self." Gallagher and Shear 407-420.
Shoemaker, David. “Personal Identity and Ethics.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2007 Edition). Ed. Edward N. Zalta. 5 July 2007. <http://plato.standord.edu/archives/spr2007/entries/identity-ethics/>
Shoemaker, Sydney. "Survival and the Importance of Identity." Kolak and Martin 267-272.
Wilkes,
Kathleen. Real People: Personal Identity Without
Thought Experiments.
Williams, Bernard. "The Self and the Future." Kolak and Martin 181-192.